Adversarial Decision Making: Choosing Between Models Constructed by Interested Parties Luke Froeb†

Bernhard Ganglmair‡ † Vanderbilt ‡ University

Steven Tschantz†

University

of Texas at Dallas

March 24, 2016

1 / 27

Outline 







Research Question: How good is adversarial decision-making? Model: Litigation as a persuasion game - Evidence (produced and discovered) is given - Parties compete to explain what it means - Court chooses most credible explanation Results: we explain . . . - why adversaries interpret evidence differently; - how such interpretations affect decisions; - and compare adversarial and inquisitorial decision making. Answer: adversarial decision making performs (surprisingly?) well 2 / 27

General Motivation Two stages of adversarial justice: 



Evidence production: parties produce and report evidence Decision making: court chooses between alternative interpretations of the evidence, constructed by interested parties

Question 1 How does adversarial decision making compare to an inquisitorial alternative?

3 / 27

Specific Motivation Case: OFT vs. Imperial Tobacco (2011) 







OFT: Vague (not falsifiable) anticompetitive theory (obfuscation as trial strategy) Imperial: Two years to “pin down” implications of OFT theory Fact witnesses rebutted OFT theory - OFT asked permission to change theory in middle of case Decision: Tribunal quashed £112m fine

Question 2 When is obfuscation an optimal strategy? 4 / 27

Litigation as a Persuasion Game - “It is your job to sort the information before trial, organize it, simplify it and present it to the jury in a simple model that explains what happened and why you are entitled to a favorable verdict.” - “Remember that there is a lawyer on the other side who will be trying to sell the jury a story that contradicts yours. . . . If both sides do competent jobs, the jury will have to choose between two competing versions of events . . . ” Tanford (2009) Indiana University Law School classroom material; emphasis added

5 / 27

Model: Principal and Two Agents







Decision-making principal (e.g., Court) solicits advice from agents with opposing interests to interpret evidence (e.g., Plaintiff P and Defendant D) - relies on expertise of agents to construct models of evidence-generating process Principal lacks expertise to construct her own model, but can assess credibility of agents’ models Principal’s objective: choose the most credible model and implement it

6 / 27

Metaphor to Statistical Model Selection   



Court analogous to researcher Evidence analogous to data, z¯ = (z1 , z2 , ..., zn ) Parties’ interpretations Zs analogous to models of data-generating process - Zs ∼ Fs (µs , σs ) where µs is unknown liability, damages, or probability of guilt Credibility analogous to likelihood L (Zs |¯ z) =

n Y

f (zi |Zs ) for s = P, D

i=1 

Court choosing more credible interpretation is analogous to researcher choosing more likely model, e.g., for plaintiff if LP > LD . 7 / 27

Inquisitorial Benchmark





Suppose: An inquisitorial court has ability to construct models for herself. Uses the maximum likelihood estimator, due to its optimality properties (DeGroot, 1970): ZM L ≡ arg max L (Z|¯ z) Z∈F

where F is the set of admissible models and µM L is the “most likely” damage estimate

8 / 27

Perfect (Adversarial) Court Probability of a plaintiff win:   for LP > LD 1 1 θ = /2 for LP = LD   0 for LP < LD Damages (paid by defendant to plaintiff)   for LP > LD µP µ ˆ = 1/2 µP + 1/2 µD for LP = LD   µD for LP < LD .

9 / 27

Perfect Court (cont.)

Adversarial equilibrium: ZP = ZD = ZM L  

Parties choose same, most likely model ZM L Similar result found in final-offer arbitration, where parties make the same utility maximizing offer (Crawford, 1979).

Adversarial outcome of a “perfect court” is equivalent to the inquisitorial benchmark

10 / 27

Noisy (Adversarial) Court 

Court’s “perceived” likelihood = signal × noise: fP = LP exp ξP L fD = LD exp ξD L



where ξP and ξD are “noise”, Gumbel(0, 1/λ) distributed Probability of a plaintiff win: fP > L fD ) = θ˜ = Pr(L



LPλ . LPλ + LDλ

This signal × noise specification used by - McFadden(1974), Tullock (1980), McKelvey and Palfrey (1995), Skaperdas and Vaidya (2012) 11 / 27

Noisy Court: Three Special Cases

λ=0 λ=1 λ→∞

Coin toss; uninformative Tullock lottery Perfect Court and inquisitorial benchmark

12 / 27

Noisy Court: Outcomes 

Expected court decision (i.e., damages): λ λ  ˜ + 1 − θ˜ µ = LP · µP + LD · µD µ ˆ(ZP , ZD ) = θµ P D LPλ + LDλ



Variance of decision:  2 Var(ˆ µ) = θ˜ 1 − θ˜ µP − µD



Plaintiff faces tradeoff: - A model with a bigger µP , increases payoff following a win . . . - but also reduces probability of a win, fP > L fD ). Pr(L - Analogously for defendant. 13 / 27

Nash Equilibrium

  

Plaintiff prefers high µ ˆ; defendant prefers low µ ˆ. Strategies are Zs from an admissible set F Nash equilibrium defined as: Plaintiff: Defendant:

∗ ∗ µ ˆ(ZP∗ , ZD )≥µ ˆ(ZP , ZD ) ∀ZP ∈ F ∗ ∗ ∗ µ ˆ(ZP , ZD ) ≤ µ ˆ(ZP , ZD ) ∀ZD ∈ F

14 / 27

Model Parameterization







Evidence is vector z¯ of n independent draws zi ∈ (0, 1) with sample mean µ ¯ zi drawn from Beta(α, β) distribution α - with mean µ = E(zi ) = α+β - with variance σ 2 = Var(zi ) = (α+β)2αβ (1+α+β) Agents s = P, D chooses model Zs = (αs , βs ) to explain evidence vector z¯.

15 / 27

Shading, Obfuscation, and Bias Result Both parties “shade” the evidence in their favor so that 0 < µD∗ < µM L < µP∗ < 1.

Result The party with less favorable evidence follows an “obfuscation strategy” and chooses a model with (i) a location further away from the most likely model and (ii) with a spread larger than its rival’s.

Result The court’s assessment of liability is biased in favor of the party with, on average, less favorable evidence. 16 / 27

Numerical Example: Evidence is (1/5, 1/2) f (z; α, β) ∗ µD

3

µP∗

Plaintiff Defendant Court

2

1 µM L µ ˆ

z

0 0

0.2

0.4

0.6

0.8

1

17 / 27

Numerical Example   



Zs = (αs , βs ) z¯ = (1/5, 1/2) Equilibrium strategies - µP = 0.51, σP2 = 0.04. - µD = 0.25, σD2 = 0.02. Court decision - Probability of a plaintiff win: θ˜ = 0.43 - Likelihood ratio LP /LD = 0.76 - Bias (relative to inquisitorial benchmark): µ ˆ = 0.36 > 0.35 = µM L

18 / 27

As Court Noise Shrinks

Result As court noise disappears, λ → ∞, (i) the parties models converge to the maximum likelihood estimator, µs → µM L , for s = P, D, as does the court’s estimator, µ ˆ → µM L ; and (ii) the probability of a plaintiff win approaches 50%, θ˜ → 1/2. The court’s estimator converges faster than do the models of the parties.

19 / 27

As Court Noise Shrinks

Var(ˆ µ)

µ 0.5

θ˜ 0.5

0.015

0.475

0.01

0.4

0.45

0.005

0.425

0.3

λ 1

10

(a) µ

100

λ

0 1

10

(b) V ar(ˆ µ)

100

λ

0.4 1

10

100

(c) θ˜

20 / 27

As Amount of Evidence Grows

Result As the amount of evidence increases, n → ∞, the court’s estimator converges in probability to the true µ = α/α+β , as do the models of the parties, µs → α/α+β for s = P, D.

21 / 27

As Amount of Evidence Grows

θ˜

Var(ˆ µ)

∆µ

0.5

0.015

0.01

0.01

0.45

0.005 0.005

n

0 1

10

(d) µ

100

n

0 1

10

(e) V ar(ˆ µ)

100

n

0.4 1

10

100

(f) θ˜

22 / 27

Discussion: Why This Model? 

More realistic than scientific inquiry with Hypothesis ⇒ Evidence ⇒ Decision Instead: hypotheses (models) strategically chosen to influence decisions with Evidence ⇒ Hypothesis ⇒ Decision



 

Captures trade-off: Claims further from data are less credible Positive justification: explains competing claims Prediction: Pr(plaintiff win) → 1/2 as court noise disappears or more evidence is available 23 / 27

Answers to Motivating Questions Question 1 Adversarial decision making looks good  Bias small, especially when compared to models chosen by parties  Bias arises only when likelihood is asymmetric  Bias and variance disappear with better court decisions, more evidence

Question 2 Obfuscation arises when likelihood is asymmetric  Party with location further from the evidence chooses a larger spread 24 / 27

Please send any comments or suggestions to [email protected], [email protected], or [email protected]

25 / 27

Appendix: General Persuasion Game  



Players: L (“left”) and R (“right”) Strategies: advice is a pair ai = (xi , yi ) - yi is the “location” of the frame: yi ∈ R - xi is the “incredibility” of the frame (inverse of credibility χi ): xL ∈ R− and xR ∈ R+ Expected Payoffs: - the credibility-weighted average of the locations:

yˆ(aL , aR ) =



wR wL yR + yL wR + wL wR + wL

withwi = 1/|xi |

- Decision yˆ(aL , aR ) is y-intercept of the line connecting the advices of the agents (see figure) Both players try to maximize slope 26 / 27

Appendix: Parameterized µ = “type” 0.8

0.6 µ ˆ

AL

AR

0.4

0.2

µM L

1/χ = “incredibility” −4

−3

−2

−1

1

2

3

4

27 / 27

Adversarial Decision Making: Choosing Between ...

Mar 24, 2016 - “It is your job to sort the information before trial, organize it, simplify it and present it to the jury in a simple model that explains what happened ...

270KB Sizes 1 Downloads 234 Views

Recommend Documents

Intuitive Decision Making
Of course, business is not a game, and much ... business decisions I ultimately rely on my intuition. .... (9 a.m.-5 p.m. ET) at the phone numbers listed below.

SITE-BASED DECISION-MAKING TEAM
Mar 26, 2013 - Roll Call. Members: Sydney Travis, Kate Grindon, Renee Romaine, Chris ... approved with one correction to roll call name. ... Old Business.

Medical Decision Making
2009; 29; 61 originally published online Feb 4, 2009;. Med Decis Making ... Annette M. O'Connor, PhD, France Le´gare´, MD, PhD. Background. Decisional conflict is ... making research programs, predictor variables and outcomes assessed ...

SITE-BASED DECISION-MAKING TEAM
Meyzeek Middle School. SITE-BASED DECISION-MAKING TEAM. Tuesday, 26 March 2013. 5:00 PM YSC Conference Room. I. Call to Order. -The meeting was ...

SITE-BASED DECISION-MAKING TEAM
Mar 26, 2013 - email today's agenda and approved minutes from the previous meeting(s) to Ms. Shawna ... Ad Hoc i. Scheduling Committee ii. Budget Committee. VII. Speakers on Non-Action Items. VIII. Old Business. • Parent Terms of Office (Lisa Runkl

decision making .pdf
Page 3 of 31. decision making .pdf. decision making .pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying decision making .pdf. Page 1 of 31.

Choosing between Axioms, Rules and Queries ...
and construct the desired data integration from an RDF datastore. Using a ... relationships between a document and its authors into a co-maker (co-author).

Twelve Considerations in Choosing between Gaussian ...
many decisions to be made in designing an IT2 FLC. One of .... the model-driven approach, whereas trapezoidal IT2 FSs can ...... Making Subjective Judgments.

Medical Decision Making
Sep 6, 2007 - HEALTH CARE DISPARITIES ... Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality to con- .... Hocine Tighouart, MS, Harry P. Selker, MD, MSPH.

Heuristic Decision Making
Nov 15, 2010 - and probability cannot, such as NP-complete. (computationally .... The program on the adaptive decision maker (Payne et al. 1993) is built on the assumption that heuris- tics achieve a beneficial trade-off between ac- curacy and effort

Steganographic Generative Adversarial Networks
3National Research University Higher School of Economics (HSE) ..... Stacked convolutional auto-encoders for steganalysis of digital images. In Asia-Pacific ...

staff involvement in decision-making Accounts
Apr 12, 2016 - Employees at various levels have decision-making authority and influence appropriate to their position. Staff involvement in decision-making ...

012313 CPC decision making process.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. 012313 CPC ...