Dynamic Approaches to Cognition

243

Hobson, J. A. (1988). The Dreaming Brain. New York: Basic Books. Hobson, J. A. (1990). Activation, input source, and modulation: A neurocognitive model of the state of the brain-mind. In R. Bootzin, J. Kihlstrom, and D. Schacter, Eds., Sleep and Cognition. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, pp. 25–40. Hobson, J. A. (1994). The Chemistry of Conscious States. Boston: Little Brown. Hobson, J. A., and R. W. McCarley. (1977). The brain as a dreamstate generator: An activation-synthesis hypothesis of the dream process. Am. J. Psychiat. 134: 1335–1348. Hobson, J. A., E. Hoffman, R. Helfand, and D. Kostner. (1987). Dream bizarreness and the activation-synthesis hypothesis. Human Neurobiology 6: 157–164. Llinas, R., and D. Pare. (1991). Commentary on dreaming and wakefulness. Neuroscience 44: 521–535. Solms, M. (1997). The Neuropsychology of Dreams: A ClinicoAnatomical Study. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Dynamic Approaches to Cognition

Figure 2a. Three-dimensional state space defined by the values for

brain activation (A), input source and strength (I), and mode of processing (M). It is theoretically possible for the system to be at any point in the state space, and an infinite number of state conditions is conceivable. In practice the system is normally constrained to a boomerang-like path from the back upper right in waking (high A, I, and M), through the center in NREM (intermediate A, I, and M) to the front lower right in REM sleep (high A, low I, and M). Figure 2b. (A) Movement through the state space during the sleep

cycle. (B) Segments of the state space associated with some normal, pathological, and artificial conditions of the brain.

See also CONSCIOUSNESS; CONSCIOUSNESS, NEUROBIOLOGY OF; LIMBIC SYSTEM; NEUROTRANSMITTERS —J. Allan Hobson

References and Further Readings Aserinsky, E., and N. Kleitman. (1953). Regularly occurring periods of eye motility and concomitant phenomena during sleep. Science 118: 273–274. Foulkes, D. (1985). Dreaming: A Cognitive-Psychological Analysis. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Freud, S. (1900). The Interpretation of Dreams. Trans. J. Strachey. New York: Basic Books.

The dynamical approach to cognition is a confederation of research efforts bound together by the idea that natural cognition is a dynamical phenomenon and best understood in dynamical terms. This contrasts with the “law of qualitative structure” (Newell and Simon 1976) governing orthodox or “classical” cognitive science, which holds that cognition is a form of digital COMPUTATION. The idea of mind as dynamical can be traced as far back as David HUME, and it permeates the work of psychologists such as Lewin and Tolman. The contemporary dynamical approach, however, is conveniently dated from the early cybernetics era (e.g., Ashby 1952). In subsequent decades dynamical work was carried out within programs as diverse as ECOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY, synergetics, morphodynamics, and neural net research. In the 1980s, three factors— growing dissatisfaction with the classical approach, developments in the pure mathematics of nonlinear dynamics, and increasing availability of computer hardware and software for simulation—contributed to a flowering of dynamical research, particularly in connectionist form (Smolensky 1988). By the 1990s, it was apparent that the dynamical approach has sufficient power, scope, and cohesion to count as a research paradigm in its own right (Port and van Gelder 1995). In the prototypical case, the dynamicist focuses on some particular aspect of cognition and proposes an abstract dynamical system as a model of the processes involved. The behavior of the model is investigated using dynamical systems theory, often aided by simulation on digital computers. A close match between the behavior of the model and empirical data on the target phenomenon confirms the hypothesis that the target is itself dynamical in nature, and that it can be understood in the same dynamical terms. Consider, for example, how we make decisions. One possibility is that in our heads there are symbols representing various options and the probabilities and values of their outcomes; our brains then crank through an ALGORITHM for determining a choice (see RATIONAL DECISIONMAKING). But this classical approach has difficulty

244

Dynamic Approaches to Cognition

accounting for the empirical data, partly because it cannot accommodate temporal issues and other relevant factors such as affect and context. Dynamical models treat the process of DECISION-MAKING as one in which numerical variables evolve interactively over time. Such models, it is claimed, can explain a wider range of data and do so more accurately (see, e.g., Busemeyer and Townsend 1993; Leven and Levine 1996). A better understanding of dynamical work can be gained by highlighting some of its many differences with classical cognitive science. Most obviously, dynamicists take cognitive agents to be dynamical systems as opposed to digital conputers. A dynamical system for current purposes is a set of quantitative variables changing continually, concurrently, and interdependently over quantitative time in accordance with dynamical laws described by some set of equations. Hand in hand with this first commitment goes the belief that dynamics provides the right tools for understanding cognitive processes. Dynamics in this sense includes the traditional practice of dynamical modeling, in which scientists attempt to understand natural phenomena via abstract dynamical models; such modeling makes heavy use of calculus and differential or difference equations. It also includes dynamical systems theory, a set of concepts, proofs, and methods for understanding the behavior of systems in general and dynamical systems in particular. A central insight of dynamical systems theory is that behavior can be understood geometrically, that is, as a matter of position and change of position in a space of possible overall states of the system. The behavior can then be described in terms of attractors, transients, stability, coupling, bifurcations, chaos, and so forth—features largely invisible from a classical perspective. Dynamicists and classicists also diverge over the general nature of cognition and cognitive agents. The pivotal issue here is probably the role of time. Although all cognitive scientists understand cognition as something that happens over time, dynamicists see cognition as being in time, that is, as an essentially temporal phenomenon. This is manifested in many ways. The time variable in dynamical models is not a mere discrete order, but a quantitative, sometimes continuous approximation to the real time of natural events. Details of timing (durations, rates, synchronies, etc.) are taken to be essential to cognition itself rather than incidental details. Cognition is seen not as having a sequential cyclic (sensethink-act) structure, but rather as a matter of continuous and continual coevolution. The subtlety and complexity of cognition is found not at a time in elaborate static structures, but rather in time in the flux of change itself. Dynamicists also emphasize SITUATEDNESS/EMBEDDEDNESS. Natural cognition is always environmentally embedded, corporeally embodied, and neurally “embrained.” Classicists typically set such considerations aside (Clark 1997). Dynamicists, by contrast, tend to see cognitive processes as collective achievements of brains in bodies in contexts. Their language—dynamics—can be used to describe change in the environment, bodily movements, and neurobiological processes (e.g., Bingham 1995; Wright and Liley 1996). This enables them to offer integrated accounts of cognition as a dynamical phenomenon in a dynamical world.

In classical cognitive science, symbolic representations and their algorithmic manipulations are the basic building blocks. Dynamical models usually also incorporate representations, but reconceive them as dynamical entities (e.g., system states, or trajectories shaped by attractor landscapes). Representations tend to be seen as transient, contextdependent stabilities in the midst of change, rather than as static, context-free, permanent units. Interestingly, some dynamicists claim to have developed wholly representationfree models, and they conjecture that representation will turn out to play much less of a role in cognition than has traditionally been supposed (e.g., Skarda 1986; Wheeler forthcoming). The differences between the dynamical and classical approaches should not be exaggerated. The dynamical approach stands opposed to what John Haugeland has called “Good Old Fashioned AI” (Haugeland 1985). However, dynamical systems may well be performing computation in some other sense (e.g., analog computation or “real” computation; Blum, Shub, and Smale 1989; Siegelmann and Sontag 1994). Also, dynamical systems are generally effectively computable. (Note that something can be computable without being a digital computer.) Thus, there is considerable middle ground between pure GOFAI and an equally extreme dynamicism (van Gelder forthcoming). How does the dynamical approach relate to connectionism? In a word, they overlap. Connectionist networks are generally dynamical systems, and much of the best dynamical research is connectionist in form (e.g., Beer 1995). However, the way many connectionists structure and interpret their systems is dominated by broadly computational preconceptions (e.g., Rosenberg and Sejnowski 1987). Conversely, many dynamical models of cognition are not connectionist networks. Connectionism is best seen as straddling a more fundamental opposition between dynamical and classical cognitive science. Chaotic systems are a special sort of dynamical system, and chaos theory is just one branch of dynamics. So far, only a small proportion of work in dynamical cognitive science has made any serious use of chaos theory. Therefore the dynamical approach should not be identified with the use of chaos theory or related notions such as fractals. Still, chaotic dynamics surely represents a frontier of fascinating possibilities for cognitive science (Garson 1996). The dynamical approach stands or falls on its ability to deliver the best models of particular aspects of cognition. In any given case its ability to do this is a matter for debate among the relevant specialists. Currently, many aspects of cognition—e.g., story comprehension—are well beyond the reach of dynamical treatment. Nevertheless, a provisional consensus seems to be emerging that some significant range of cognitive phenomena will turn out to be dynamical, and that a dynamical perspective enriches our understanding of cognition more generally. See also COGNITIVE MODELING, CONNECTIONIST; COMPUTATION AND THE BRAIN; COMPUTATIONAL THEORY OF MIND; CONNECTIONIST APPROACHES TO LANGUAGE; NEURAL NETWORKS; RULES AND REPRESENTATIONS —Tim Van Gelder

Dynamic Programming

References Ashby, R. (1952). Design for a Brain. London: Chapman and Hall. Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspective on agentenvironment interaction. Artificial Intelligence 72: 173–215. Bingham, G. (1995). Dynamics and the problem of event recognition. In R. Port and T. van Gelder, Eds., Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Blum, L., M. Shub, and S. Smale. (1989). On a theory of computation and complexity over the real numbers: NP completeness, recursive functions and universal machines. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 21: 1–49. Busemeyer, J. R., and J. T. Townsend. (1993). Decision field theory: A dynamic-cognitive approach to decision making in an uncertain environment. Psychological Review 100: 432–459. Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Garson, J. (1996). Cognition poised at the edge of chaos: a complex alternative to a symbolic mind. Philosophical Psychology 9: 301–321. Haugeland, J. (1985). Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Leven, S. J., and D. S. Levine. (1996). Multiattribute decision making in context: A dynamic neural network methodology. Cognitive Science 20: 271–299. Newell, A., and H. Simon. (1976). Computer science as empirical enquiry: Symbols and search. Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery 19: 113–126. Port, R., and T. J. van Gelder. (1995). Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Rosenberg, C. R., and T. J. Sejnowski. (1987). Parallel networks that learn to pronounce English text. Complex Systems 1. Siegelmann, H. T., and E. D. Sontag. (1994). Analog computation via neural networks. Theoretical Computer Science 131: 331– 360. Skarda, C. A. (1986). Explaining behavior: Bringing the brain back in. Inquiry 29: 187–202. Smolensky, P. (1988). On the proper treatment of connectionism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11: 1–74. van Gelder, T. J. (Forthcoming). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. Wheeler, M. (Forthcoming). The Next Step: Beyond Cartesianism in the Science of Cognition. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Wright, J. J., and D. T. J. Liley. (1996). Dynamics of the brain at global and microscopic scales: Neural networks and the EEG. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19.

Further Readings Giunti, M. (1997). Computation, Dynamics, and Cognition. New York: Oxford University Press. Gregson, R. A. M. (1988). Nonlinear Psychophysical Dynamics. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Haken, H., and M. Stadler, Eds. (1990). Synergetics of Cognition. Berlin: Springer. Horgan, T. E., and J. Tienson. (1996). Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jaeger, H. (1996). Dynamische systeme in der kognitionswissenschaft. Kognitionswissenschaft 5: 151–174. Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic Patterns: The Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Port, R., and T. J. van Gelder. (1995). Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

245

Sulis, W., and A. Combs, Eds. (1996). Nonlinear Dynamics in Human Behavior. Singapore: World Scientific. Thelen, E., and L. B. Smith. (1993). A Dynamics Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Vallacher, R., and A. Nowak, Eds. (1993). Dynamical Systems in Social Psychology. New York: Academic Press. Wheeler, M. (Forthcoming). The Next Step: Beyond Cartesianism in the Science of Cognition. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

Dynamic Programming Some problems can be structured into a collection of small problems, each of which can be solved on the basis of the solution of some of the others. The process of working a solution back through the subproblems in order to reach a final answer is called dynamic programming. This general algorithmic technique is applied in a wide variety of areas, from optimizing airline schedules to allocating cell-phone bandwidth to justifying typeset text. Its most common and relevant use, however, is for PLANNING optimal paths through state-space graphs, in order, for example, to find the best routes between cities in a map. In the simplest case, consider a directed, weighted graph < S, A, T, L>, where S is the set of nodes or “states” of the graph, and A is a set of arcs or “actions” that may be taken from each state. The state that is reached by taking action a in state s is described as T(s,a); the positive length of the a arc from state s is written L(s,a). Let g ∈ S be a desired goal state. Given such a structure, we might want to find the shortest path from a particular state to the goal state, or even to find the shortest paths from each of the states to the goal. In order to make it easy to follow shortest paths, we will use dynamic programming to compute a distance function, D(s), that gives the distance from each state to the goal state. The ALGORITHM is as follows: D(s): = large D(g): = 0 Loop |S| times Loop for s in S D(s): = mina ∈ AL(s,a) + D(T(s,a)) end loop end loop We start by initializing D(s) = large to be an overestimate of the distance between s and g (except in the case of D(g), for which it is exact). Now, we want to improve iteratively the estimates of D(s). The inner loop updates the value for each state s to be the minimum over the outgoing arcs of L(s,a) + D(T(s,a)); the first term is the known distance of the first arc and the second term is the estimated distance from the resulting state to the goal. The outer loop is executed as many times as there are states. The character of this algorithm is as follows: Initially, only D(g) is correct. After the first iteration, D(s) is correct for all states whose shortest path to the goal is one step long. After |S| iterations, it is correct for all states. Note that if L was uniformly 1, then all the states that are i steps from the goal would have correct D values after the ith iteration; however, it may be possible for some state s to be one step

Dynamic Approaches to Cognition - Semantic Scholar

neurocognitive model of the state of the brain-mind. In R. Bootzin, J. Kihlstrom ... nition is a dynamical phenomenon and best understood in dynamical terms. ... cal research, particularly in connectionist form (Smolensky. 1988). By the 1990s, it ...

30KB Sizes 6 Downloads 440 Views

Recommend Documents

Dynamic Approaches to Cognition - Semantic Scholar
structure” (Newell and Simon 1976) governing orthodox or. “classical” cognitive science, which ... pirical data on the target phenomenon confirms the hypothe- sis that the target is itself .... Artificial Intelligence 72: 173–215. Bingham, G.

Irrationality and Cognition - Semantic Scholar
Feb 28, 2006 - Page 1 ... For example, my own system OSCAR (Pollock 1995) is built to cognize in certain ... Why would anyone build a cognitive agent in.

Irrationality and Cognition - Semantic Scholar
Feb 28, 2006 - “When you do have a good argument for a conclusion, you should accept the conclusion”, and “Be ... For example, my own system OSCAR (Pollock 1995) is built to cognize in certain ways, ..... get a ticket, etc. Hierarchical ...

Pattern-based approaches to semantic relation ... - Semantic Scholar
assessment of semantic information that can be automatically extracted from machine readable dictionaries (MRDs). In fact, a large body of research has been ...

Information processing, computation, and cognition - Semantic Scholar
Apr 9, 2010 - 2. G. Piccinini, A. Scarantino. 1 Information processing, computation, and the ... In recent years, some cognitive scientists have attempted to get around the .... used in computer science and computability theory—the same notion that

implementing dynamic semantic resolution - Semantic Scholar
testing of a rule of inference called dynamic semantic resolution is then ... expressed in a special form, theorem provers are able to generate answers, ... case of semantic resolution that Robinson called hyper-resolution uses a static, trivial mode

Information processing, computation, and cognition - Semantic Scholar
Apr 9, 2010 - Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010. Abstract Computation ... purposes, and different purposes are legitimate. Hence, all sides of ...... In comes the redness of a ripe apple, out comes approaching. But organisms do ...

implementing dynamic semantic resolution - Semantic Scholar
expressed in a special form, theorem provers are able to generate answers, .... First Australian Undergraduate Students' Computing Conference, 2003 page 109 ...

Stable communication through dynamic language - Semantic Scholar
texts in which particular words are used, or the way in which they are ... rules of grammar can only be successfully transmit- ted if the ... are much more likely to pass through the bottleneck into the ... ternal world is not sufficient to avoid the

Dynamic Moral Hazard and Stopping - Semantic Scholar
Jan 3, 2011 - agencies “frequently” to find a wide variety of workers. ... 15% and 20% of searches in the pharmaceutical sector fail to fill a post (Pharmafocus. (2007)). ... estate agent can affect buyer arrival rates through exerting marketing

Somatosensory Integration Controlled by Dynamic ... - Semantic Scholar
Oct 19, 2005 - voltage recording and representative spike waveforms (red) and mean ..... Note the deviation of the experimental data points from the unity line.

Dynamic Moral Hazard and Stopping - Semantic Scholar
Jan 3, 2011 - agencies “frequently” to find a wide variety of workers. ... 15% and 20% of searches in the pharmaceutical sector fail to fill a post (Pharmafocus. (2007)). ... estate agent can affect buyer arrival rates through exerting marketing

Optimal Dynamic Hedging of Cliquets - Semantic Scholar
May 1, 2008 - Kapoor, V., L. Cheung, C. Howley, Equity securitization; Risk & Value, Special Report, Structured. Finance, Standard & Poor's, (2003). Laurent, J.-P., H. Pham, Dynamic Programming and mean-variance hedging, Finance and Stochastics, 3, 8

Exploring Dynamic Branch Prediction Methods - Semantic Scholar
Department of Computer Science and Engineering, Michigan State University ... branch prediction methods and analyze which kinds of information are important ...

Secure Dependencies with Dynamic Level ... - Semantic Scholar
evolve due to declassi cation and subject current level ... object classi cation and the subject current level. We ...... in Computer Science, Amsterdam, The Nether-.

Exploring Dynamic Branch Prediction Methods - Semantic Scholar
Department of Computer Science and Engineering, Michigan State University. {wuming .... In the course of pursuing the most important factors to improve prediction accuracy, only simulation can make .... basic prediction mechanism. Given a ...

Stable communication through dynamic language - Semantic Scholar
In E. Briscoe, editor, Linguistic. Evolution through Language Acquisition: Formal and Computational Models, pages 173–203. Cam- bridge University Press ...

Optimal Dynamic Hedging of Cliquets - Semantic Scholar
May 1, 2008 - some presumed mid price of vanillas results in a replicating strategy for the exotic. Risk management departments (also called Risk Control) are charged with feeding the pricing model sensitivity outputs into a VaR model, and generally

Two Approaches for the Generalization of Leaf ... - Semantic Scholar
Definition 2.1 Let G be a graph and F a subgraph of G. An edge e of F is called ..... i=1 Bi. By the same proof technique as for the case m = 1, one can transform F ...

Approaches of using UML for Embedded System ... - Semantic Scholar
of constraints like performance, cost, power consumption, size and weight etc. The platform of implementation may be ... signal processing of audio and video, wired and wireless communication have led to complex embedded ..... for Proposal: UML. Prof

Approaches of using UML for Embedded System ... - Semantic Scholar
and software. Choice of system components depends upon optimality of. - Implementation of function. - Analysis of alternatives in both hardware and software domains. Specification of flexible hardware- ... These systems are integration of subsystems

Two Approaches for the Generalization of Leaf ... - Semantic Scholar
Center for Combinatorics, Nankai University, .... set E, and a specified vertex r ∈ V , which we call the root of G. If X is a .... Then, contract G2 into one vertex ¯r.

Dictionary-Based Pitch Tracking with Dynamic ... - Semantic Scholar
Sep 14, 2014 - The use of dynamic programming in PDAs itself, however, is not new: the technique is ... In speech, pitch is meaningful only in voiced segments and ... algorithms (VDA) can be incorporated at various stages of the. PDA, or be ...

Marriage and Career: The Dynamic Decisions of ... - Semantic Scholar
I especially want to thank Simcha Srebnik for computer support. I also thank the Maurice Falk ...... White-collar wage mis- match adjustment parameter (a3). J.285.