Fixed-step anonymous overtaking and catching-up∗ Geir B. Asheim†

Kuntal Banerjee‡

January 20, 2009

Abstract We investigate criteria for evaluating infinite utility streams that satisfy Fixedstep anonymity and includes some notion of overtaking or catching-up. We do so in a generalized setting which do not require us to specify the underlying finitedimensional criterion (e.g., utilitarianism or leximin). We present axiomatizations that rely on weaker axioms than those in the literature, and which in one case is new. We also provide a complete analysis of the relationships between the symmetric parts of these criteria and likewise for the asymmetric parts.

Keywords and Phrases: Intergenerational justice, Utilitarianism, Leximin. JEL Classification Numbers: D63, D71. ∗

Both authors thank Tapan Mitra for stimulating discussions through many years on topics

related to the present paper, and we wish him many more years of fruitful research. Banerjee hopes that Tapanda may provide future generations of theorists with the same compassionate mentoring that he himself has been the fortunate recipient of. We also thank Kohei Kamaga for helpful comments, and Asheim gratefully acknowledges the hospitality of the Department of Economics at University of California, Santa Barbara, where this research was completed. †

Department of Economics, University of Oslo, P.O. Box 1095 Blindern, N-0317 Oslo, Norway

(tel: 47-22855498; fax: 47-22855035; e-mail: [email protected]). ‡

Department of Economics, Florida Atlantic University, 777 Glades Road, Boca Raton, FL

33431, USA (e-mail: [email protected]).

1

Introduction

Recent contributions have suggested new social welfare relations for the purpose of evaluating infinite utility streams representing the welfare levels of an infinite and countable number of generations. Notable examples are Basu and Mitra (2007), who extend the utilitarian ordering on a finite dimensional Euclidian space to the infinite dimensional case, and Bossert, Sprumont and Suzumura (2007), who do likewise for the leximin ordering. The fact that both these relations are incomplete (since they can only compare utility streams whose tails are Pareto comparable beyond some finite time) motivates the following question: How can their symmetric and asymmetric parts be extended, so that a larger set of pairs of utility streams becomes comparable. This is the question we consider in the present paper. The social welfare relations of Basu and Mitra (2007) and Bossert, Sprumont and Suzumura (2007) satisfy Finite anonymity (ensuring equal treatment of generations by letting social evaluation be insensitive to finite permutations of utilities) and Strong Pareto (ensuring sensitivity for the interests for each generation). Work by Lauwers (2007) and Zame (2007) confirms the following conjecture, suggested by Fleurbaey and Michel (2003): it is not possible to construct and describe a complete and transitive binary relation on the set of infinite utility streams which satisfies the axioms of Finite anonymity and Strong Pareto. Hence, if we are want to be consider constructible social welfare relations satisfying Finite anonymity and Strong Pareto, then completeness is an unreachable goal. Still, more comparability can be achieved (i) by strengthening Finite anonymity and (ii) by including some notion of overtaking or catching-up (in the tradition of Atsumi, 1965; von Weizs¨acker, 1965). Many authors (see, e.g., Lauwers, 1997a; Liedekerke and Lauwers, 1997; Fleurbaey and Michel, 2003) have argued that a stronger axiom than Finite anonymity is needed to reflect intergenerational equity in intertemporal preferences. However, as is well-known, imposing insensitivity to all permutations of utilities contradicts

1

Strong Pareto. Therefore, strengthening Finite anonymity while keeping Strong Pareto must amount to adding insensitivity to some, but not all, infinite permutations. The set of fixed-step permutations, introduced by Lauwers (1997b) and analyzed by Fleurbaey and Michel (2003), is a strict superset of the set of finite permutations.1 It is a consequence of the general results of Mitra and Basu (2007) that Fixed-step anonymity, in the sense of insensitivity to fixed-step permutations, is consistent with Strong Pareto. Fixed-step anonymity has subsequently been added to the criterion of Basu and Mitra (2007) (by Banerjee, 2006) and to the the criterion of Bossert, Sprumont and Suzumura (2007) (by Kamaga and Kojima, 2008a). Asheim and Tungodden (2004) analyze two utilitarian overtaking and catchingup criteria (as introduced by Atsumi, 1965, and von Weizs¨acker, 1965) and two leximin overtaking and catching-up criteria. The two former are compatible with but lead to more comparability than Basu and Mitra’s (2007) criterion, while the two latter do likewise to Bossert, Sprumont and Suzumura’s (2007) criterion. While extending Finite anonymity amounts to less sensitivity to the sequencing of utilities, overtaking and catching-up criteria introduce more sensitivity to the order in which utilities appear. Indeed, Kamaga and Kojima (2008b) show that Fixed-step anonymity cannot be added to the utilitarian and leximin catching-up criteria. In this paper we investigate infinite-dimensional criteria that satisfy Fixed-step anonymity and includes some notion of overtaking or catching-up. Following work of d’Aspremont (2007) and Asheim, d’Aspremont and Banerjee (2008), we do so in a generalized setting which do not require us to specify the underlying finitedimensional criterion (e.g., utilitarianism or leximin). We present axiomatizations that rely on weaker axioms than those in the literature, and which in one case is new. We also provide a complete analysis of the relationships between the symmetric parts of these criteria and likewise for the asymmetric parts. Section 2 contains 1

In a fixed-step permutation, utilities are permuted within blocks of time of equal length.

2

preliminaries, Section 3 introduces the social welfare relations and axioms we will consider, Section 4 relates the axiom, Section 5 presents the axiomatization, while Section 6 investigates the relationships between the various criteria.

2

Preliminaries

2.1

Notation and Definitions

Let N denote the set of natural numbers {1, 2, 3, ...} and R the set of real numbers. Let X denote the set Y |N| , where Y ⊆ R is an interval satisfying [0, 1] ⊆ Y . Let X be the domain of utility streams; i.e., x ≡ (x1 , x2 , . . .) ∈ X iff xn ∈ Y for all n ∈ N. Write 0 ≡ (0, 0, . . . ). For x, y ∈ X, write x ≥ y iff xi ≥ yi for all i ∈ N and x > y iff x ≥ y and x 6= y. Subsets M , N of N will refer to nonempty subsets of finite cardinality, entailing that N\M , N\N are cofinite sets (i.e., subsets of N which complements are finite). For all x ∈ X and any N ⊂ N, write x = (xN , xN\N ). For all n ∈ N, write N (n) = {1, . . . , n}. Vectors (finite as well as infinite-dimensional) are denoted by bold letters, while the components of a vector are denoted by normal font. A social welfare relation (SWR) is a reflexive and transitive binary relation defined on X (and denoted %) or Y |M | for some M ⊂ N (and denoted %M ). A social welfare order (SWO) is a complete SWR. An SWR %0 is a subrelation of SWR %00 if (a) for all x, y ∈ X, x ∼0 y ⇒ x ∼00 y, and (b) for all x, y ∈ X, x 0 y ⇒ x 00 y.

2.2

Permutations

A permutation π is a one-to-one map from N onto N. For any x ∈ X and a permutation π, we write x ◦ π = (xπ(1) , xπ(2) , . . . ) ∈ X. Permutations can be represented by a permutation matrix, P = (pij )i,j∈N , which is an infinite matrix satisfying: (1) For each i ∈ N, pij(i) = 1 for some j(i) ∈ N and pij = 0 for all j 6= j(i). 3

(2) For each j ∈ N, pi(j)j = 1 for i(j) ∈ N and pij = 0 for all i 6= i(j). Given any permutation π, there is a permutation matrix P such that for x ∈ X, x◦π = (xπ(1) , xπ(2) , . . . ) can also be written as P x in the usual matrix multiplication. Conversely, given any permutation matrix P , there is a permutation π defined by π = P a, where a = (1, 2, 3, . . . ). The set of all permutations is denoted by P. A finite permutation π is a permutation such that there is some N ⊂ N with π(i) = i for all i ∈ / N . Thus, a finite permutation matrix has pii = 1 for all i ∈ /N for some N ⊂ N. The set of all finite permutations is denoted by F. Given a permutation matrix P ∈ P and n ∈ N, we denote the n × n matrix (pij )i,j∈{1,...,n} by P (n). Let S = {P ∈ P | there is some k ∈ N such that, for each n ∈ N, P (nk) is a finite dimensional permutation matrix} denote the set of fixed-set permutations. It is easily checked that this is a group (with respect to matrix multiplication) of cyclic permutations.2

2.3

Axioms of Anonymity and Pareto

Let %M be an SWR defined on Y |M | . Throughout we will assume that %M satisfies the following anonymity condition, where the same permutation applies to the two utility vectors. Hence, we call it “relative anonymity”. In the present intergenerational context it can be interpreted as a time invariance property. Axiom m-I (m-Relative Anonymity) For all xM , yM , uN , vN ∈ Y m with M = {i1 , i2 , ..., im } ⊂ N and N = {j1 , j2 , ..., jm } ⊂ N for some m ∈ N, if there exists a 2

A permutation is cyclic if for each ei = (0, . . . , 0, 1, 0. . . . ) (with 1 at the ith place) there exists

a k ∈ N such that π k (ei ) = ei . The class of cyclic permutations is not necessarily a group, while P is a group which does not contain only cyclic permutations.

4

finite permutation π : {1, . . . , m} → {1, . . . , m} such that xiπ(k) = ujk and yiπ(k) = vjk for all k ∈ {1, . . . , m}, then xM %M yM if and only if uN %N vN . By satisfying m-I, %M depends only on the dimension |M |. We will henceforth write %m for an SWR on Y m , thereby signifying that the SWR satisfies m-I. One kind of basic axiom is the usual anonymity condition, where a permutation is applied to the one utility stream only. Axiom m-A (m-Anonymity) For all a, b ∈ Y m , if m ≥ 2 and a is a permutation of b, then a ∼m b. Since %m is transitive, m-A is equivalent to having a ∼m b whenever there exists i, j ∈ {1, . . . , m} such that ai = bj , aj = bi and ak = bk for all k 6= i, j. The m-Pareto Principle (a %Pm b if and only if a ≥ b) illustrates that m-I does not imply m-A. However, as originally shown by d’Aspremont and Gevers (1977, Lemma 4), the two axioms are equivalent if %m is complete. Lemma 1 (Asheim, d’Aspremont and Banerjee, 2008, Lemma 1) If %m with m ≥ 2 is complete, then %m satisfies m-A. The other kind of basic axiom is the Pareto condition. Axiom m-P (m-Pareto) For all a, b ∈ Y m , if a > b, then a m b. Clearly, since %m is transitive, m-P is equivalent to having a m b whenever there exists i ∈ {1, . . . , m} such that ai > bi and ak = bk for all k 6= i.

2.4

Proliferating sequences

Many well-known finite-dimensional SWRs form proliferating sequences (d’Aspremont, 2007). Examples include the m-Grading Principle (a %Sm b if and only if there exists a permutation c of b such that a ≥ c) and the utilitarian and leximin SWOs (see Asheim, d’Aspremont and Banerjee, 2008, Section 5). The structure imposed 5

by this concept on a sequence of finite-dimensional SWR enables the extension to an infinite-dimensional SWR to be analyzed at a generalized level, without considering the specific nature of the finite-dimensional counterpart. Furthermore, it allows infinite-dimensional SWRs to be defined solely on the basis of the 2-dimensional version of the underlying finite-dimensional SWR. An SWR % extends the SWR %m if, for all M ⊂ N with |M | = m and all x, y ∈ X with xi = yi for every i ∈ N\M , xM m yM implies x  y, and xM ∼m yM implies x ∼ y. Definition 1 A sequence of SWRs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 , is proliferating if any SWR % that extends %∗2 also extends %∗m for every m 6= 2.

3

Social welfare relations and axioms

Assume for the remainder of this paper that {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. This means that, for each m ∈ N, %∗m is complete and satisfies m-A (by Lemma 1) and m-P (by assumption).

3.1

Axioms

Consider the following axioms, which are requirements on infinite-dimensional SWRs stemming from properties on the corresponding finite-dimensional SWOs. We start with axioms that combines conditions for indifference and preference. Axiom WC (Weak consistency) For all x, y ∈ X, (a) if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) ∼ (yN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) for all n ≥ m, then x ∼ y; (b) if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , 0N\N (n) )  (yN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) for all n ≥ m, then x  y. Axiom SC (Strong consistency) For all x, y ∈ X, 6

(a) if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) % (yN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) for all n ≥ m, then x % y. (b) if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) % (yN (n) , 0N\N (n) ) for all n ≥ m, and for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (n) , 0N\N (n) )  (yN (n) , 0N\N (n) ), then x  y; Axiom PC (Pairwise continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) ) % y, then x % y. Axioms WC and SC were introduced by Basu and Mitra (2007), while axiom PC is due to Sakai (2008). We continue with axioms that provides conditions for indifference only. Axiom WIC (Weak indifference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) ) ∼ y for all n ≥ m, then x ∼ y. Axiom SIC (Strong indifference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) ) ∼ y, then x ∼ y. Axiom SA (Fixed-step anonymity) For all x ∈ X and all P ∈ S, x ∼ P x. Axiom WSIC (Weak fixed-step indifference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) ∼ y for all n ≥ m, then x ∼ y. Axiom WSIC1 (Weak fixed-step indifference continuity 1) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exists k ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) ∼ y for all n ∈ N, then x ∼ y. Axioms WIC and SIC were discussed in Asheim and Tungodden (2004, Section 6) and were formally introduced in the earlier working paper version of that paper. Axiom SA stems from Lauwers (1997b), and Mitra and Basu (2007) show that it can be combined with SP since it is a group of cyclic permutations. It follows from Proposition 1 below that Axiom WSIC1 is equivalent to part (ii) of Kamaga and Kojima’s (2008b) Weak fixed-step consistency axiom. 7

Finally, we come to axioms that provides conditions for preference only. Axiom SP (Strong Pareto) For all x, y ∈ X, if x > y, then x  y. Axiom WPC (Weak preference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) )  y for all n ≥ m, then x  y. Axiom WPC1 (Weak preference continuity 1) For all x, y ∈ X, if (xN (n) , yN\N (n) )  y for all n ∈ N, then x  y. Axiom SPC (Strong preference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) ) % y for all n ≥ m, and for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) )  y, then x  y. Axiom SPC1 (Strong preference continuity 1) For all x, y ∈ X, if (xN (n) , yN\N (n) ) % y for all n ∈ N, and for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) )  y, then x  y. Axiom WSPC (Weak fixed-step preference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y for all n ≥ m, then x  y. Axiom WSPC1 (Weak fixed-step preference continuity 1) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exists k ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y for all n ∈ N, then x  y. Axiom SSPC (Strong fixed-step preference continuity) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) % y for all n ≥ m, and for all k, m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y, then x  y. Axiom SSPC1 (Strong fixed-step preference continuity 1) For all x, y ∈ X, if there exists k ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) % y for all n ∈ N, and for all k, m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y, then x  y. Axioms WPC and SPC were introduced by Asheim and Tungodden (2004), and axiom WSPC1 was introduced by Kamaga and Kojima (2008b), while axiom SSPC 8

is original to the present paper.

3.2

Generalized criteria

Consider the following “generalized criteria”, which can be specialized to the utilitarian and leximin cases, since the utiliarian and leximin SWOs are proliferating sequences of Paretian SWOs. Definition 2 (Generalized overtaking) The generalized overtaking criterion %∗O generated by {%∗m }∞ m=1 satisfies, for x, y ∈ X, x ∼∗O y iff there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∼∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m; x ∗O y iff there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Definition 3 (Generalized catching-up) The generalized catching-up criterion %∗C generated by {%∗m }∞ m=1 satisfies, for x, y ∈ X, x %∗C y iff there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) %∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Definition 4 (Generalized fixed-step anonymous overtaking) The generalized fixed-step anonymous overtaking criterion %∗SAO generated by {%∗m }∞ m=1 satisfies, for x, y ∈ X, x %∗SAO y iff there exists P , Q ∈ S such that P x %∗O Qy. Definition 5 (Generalized fixed-step overtaking) The generalized fixed-step overtaking criterion %∗SO generated by {%∗m }∞ m=1 satisfies, for x, y ∈ X, x ∼∗SO y iff there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) ∼∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m; x ∗SO y iff there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Definition 6 (Generalized fixed-step catching-up) The generalized fixed-step catching-up criterion %∗SC generated by {%∗m }∞ m=1 satisfies, for x, y ∈ X, x %∗SC y iff there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) %∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. 9

In their utilitarian versions, %∗O and %∗C were introduced by Atsumi (1965) and von Weizs¨acker (1965), while the leximin versions appear in Asheim and Tungodden (2004). In its utilitarian version, %∗SC was suggested by Lauwers (1993) and further analyzed by Fleurbaey and Michel (2003), while the corresponding overtaking criterion, %∗SO , was introduced by Kamaga and Kojima (2008b). Fixed-step anonymous overtaking, %∗SAO , was also introduced by Kamaga and Kojima (2008b), who also show that the analogous fixed-step anonymous catching-up is impossible.

4

Relating axioms

Following Sakai (2008), say that an SWR % strongly extends the SWR %m if, for all M ⊂ N with |M | = m and all x, y ∈ X with xi = yi for every i ∈ N\M , xM %m yM iff x % y. The following observation is stated without proof. Lemma 2 If an SWR % extends the SWR %m and %m is complete, then % strongly extends %m . Lemma 2 implies the following condition of separable present. Proposition 1 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of SWOs and assume that % extends %∗2 . For all x, y, u, v ∈ X and M ⊂ N, (xM , uN\M ) % (yM , uN\M ) iff (xM , vN\M ) % (yM , vN\M ). It is corollary of Proposition 1 that WIC ⇔ WC(a) WPC ⇔ WC(b) WIC & SPC ⇒ SC(a) SPC ⇔ SC(b) ∗ if {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs and % extends %2 . Furthermore,

the following proposition entails that axiom WIC is superfluous. 10

Proposition 2 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs and assume that % extends %∗2 . Then axiom WIC is satisfied. Proposition 2 follows directly from part (ii) of the following lemma. Lemma 3 A proliferating sequence {%∗m }∞ m=1 of Paretian SWOs satisfies: (i) If xi = yi for some i ∈ N\M , then xM %∗|M | yM iff xM ∪{i} %∗|M |+1 yM ∪{i} . (ii) If there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∼∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m, then xn = yn for all n > m. Proof. (i) Asheim, d’Aspremont and Banerjee (2008, Lemma 3(i)). (ii) Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of SWOs with, for each m ∈ N, %∗m satisfying m-P. Assume that there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∼∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Suppose that xn 6= yn for some n > m; w.l.o.g. we can set xn > yn . Since %∗n satisfies m-P, it follows from part (i) that xN (n) ∼∗n (yN (n−1) , xn ) ∗n yN (n) , contradicting that xN (n) ∼∗n yN (n) . Hence, xi = yi for all n > m. Hence, in our context WC can be replaced by the strictly weaker axiom WPC and SC can be replaced by the strictly weaker axiom SPC. For this reason, we will not consider WC and SC when axiomatizing the generalized overtaking and catching-up criteria in the next section. Observe that axiom PC implies axiom SIC, while as shown by Asheim and Tungodden (2004, Section 6) SIC cannot be combined with SP under transitivity (see also Fleurbaey and Michel, 2003). Hence, since we will be concerned with Paretian SWRs, we will not apply axioms PC and SIC. Observe also that axioms WSIC and WSIC1 are equivalent and imply each of axioms WIC and SA. Clearly, axiom WPC implies axiom WPC1, and axiom SPC implies axiom SPC1. However, when applied to an SWR that extends %∗2 , where {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a 11

proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, the following lemma implies that axioms WPC and WPC1 are equivalent, and axioms SPC and SPC1 are equivalent. Lemma 4 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. If xN (m) ∗m yN (m) for some m ∈ N, then there exists a finite permutation matrix P (m) such ˜ N (m) = P (m)xN (m) and y ˜ N (m) = P (m)yN (m) satisfy x ˜ N (n) ∗n xN (n) for all that x n ∈ {1, . . . , m}. Proof. Let P (m) have the property that x ˜1 −˜ y1 ≥ x ˜2 −˜ y2 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜m−1 −˜ ym−1 ≥ x ˜m − y˜m , where it follows from axiom m-P and xN (m) ∗m yN (m) that x ˜1 > y˜1 . ˜ N (m) ∗m y ˜ N (m) . Assume The result is shown by induction. By the premise, x ˜ N (n) ∗n y ˜ N (n) for all n ∈ {` + 1, . . . , m}, where ` ∈ {1, . . . , m − 1}. The that x ˜ N (`) . ˜ N (`) ∗` y inductive proof is complete by showing that x ˜ N (`) by axiom m-P. ˜ N (`) > y ˜ N (`) and x ˜ N (`) ∗` y If x ˜`+1 ≥ y˜`+1 , then x ˜ N (`+1) ∗`+1 y ˜ N (`+1) by axiom m-P. It If x ˜`+1 < y˜`+1 , then (˜ xN (`) , y˜`+1 ) ∗`+1 x ˜ N (`) . ˜ N (`) ∗` y now follows from Lemma 3(i) that x An SWR that extends %∗2 , where {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, need not be able to compare x and y with x ≥ y, if for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that xn > yn . However, axiom SP is satisfied if WPC is added. It is straightforward to show that axioms WSPC and WSPC1 are equivalent, and axioms SSPC and SSPC1 are equivalent. Furthermore, axiom SSPC1 implies axiom WSPC1, which in turn implies axiom WPC. It is not true, though, that SSPC1 implies axiom SPC, while axiom SPC does imply axiom WPC. The following figures show these relationships when % is an SWR that extends %∗2 , where {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. SA ⇑ WIC ⇐ WSIC1 ⇔ WSIC 12

SP ⇑ WPC1 ⇔ WPC ⇐ WSPC1 ⇔ WSPC ⇑ SPC1

5







SPC

SSPC1

⇑ ⇔

SSPC

Axiomatizations

In the present axiomatizations of the five generalized criteria listed in Section 3.2. The axiomatizations of the first four criteria rely on weaker axioms than those provided in the literature (Asheim and Tungodden, 2004; Basu and Mitra, 2007; Kamaga and Kojima, 2008b), while the axiomatization of the final one is new. Proposition 3 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. Then an SWR % extends %∗2 and satisfies WPC1 iff %∗O is a subrelation of %. Proof. Part I: If % extends %∗2 and satisfies WPC1, then %∗O is a subrelation of %. Consider an arbitrary pair x, y ∈ X. If x ∼∗O y, then there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∼∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and, by Proposition 2, satisfies WIC, x ∼ y. If x ∗O y, then there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Let ˜ = P x and y ˜ = P y satisfy x P ∈ F have the property that x ˜1 − y˜1 ≥ x ˜2 − y˜2 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜m−1 − y˜m−1 ≥ x ˜m − y˜m , while x ˜n = xn and y˜n = yn for n > m. It now follows from ˜ N (n) ∗n y ˜ N (n) for all n ∈ N. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and Lemma 4 that x ˜y ˜ . Furthermore, %∗m satisfies A and % extends %∗m , implying satisfies WPC1, x ˜ and y ˜ ∼ y. By transitivity, x  y. that x ∼ x Part II: If %∗O is a subrelation of %, then % extends %∗2 and satisfies WPC. We omit the straightforward proof of the result that % extends %∗2 . To show that % satisfies WPC, assume that there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) )  y for all n ≥ m. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a pro13

liferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that xN (n) ∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Hence, by the definition of O , x ∗O y, and x  y since %∗O is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition WPC. Since WPC implies WPC1, parts I and II prove the proposition. Proposition 4 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. Then an SWR % extends %∗2 and satisfies SPC1 iff %∗C is a subrelation of %. Proof. Part I: If % extends %∗2 and satisfies SPC1, then %∗C is a subrelation of %. Consider an arbitrary pair x, y ∈ X. If x ∼∗C y, then there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) ∼∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and, by Proposition 2, satisfies WIC, x ∼ y. If x ∗C y, then (i) there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) %∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m, and (ii) for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that xN (n) ∗n yN (n) . Hence, we can pick m ∈ N with the property that xN (m) ∗m yN (m) and xN (n) %∗n yN (n) ˜ = P x and y ˜ = P y satisfy for all n > m. Let P ∈ F have the property that x x ˜1 − y˜1 ≥ x ˜2 − y˜2 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜m−1 − y˜m−1 ≥ x ˜m − y˜m , while x ˜n = xn and y˜n = yn for ˜ N (n) %∗n y ˜ N (n) for all n ∈ N and (ii) n > m. It now follows from Lemma 4 that (i) x ˜ N (n) . Since % extends %∗n for ˜ N (n) ∗n y for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that x ˜y ˜ . Furthermore, %∗m satisfies A and % extends all n ∈ N and satisfies SPC1, x ˜ and y ˜ ∼ y. By transitivity, x  y. %∗m , implying that x ∼ x Part II: If %∗C is a subrelation of %, then % extends %∗2 and satisfies SPC. We omit the straightforward proof of the result that % extends %∗2 . To show that % satisfies SPC, assume that there exists m ∈ N such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) ) % y for all n ≥ m, and for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (n) , yN\N (n) )  y. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that there exists m ∈ N such that xN (n) %∗n yN (n) for all n ≥ m, and for all m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that xN (n) ∗n yN (n) . Hence, by the definition of %∗C , x ∗C y, and x  y since %∗C is a subrelation of %. 14

This shows that % satisfies condition SPC. Since SPC implies SPC1, parts I and II prove the proposition. Proposition 5 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. Then an SWR % extends %∗2 and satisfies SA and WPC1 and iff %∗SAO is a subrelation of %. The proof of Proposition 5 relies on the following lemma. Lemma 5 (Kamaga and Kojima, 2008b) Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. The generalized fixed-step anonymous overtaking criterion %∗SAO generated by {%∗m }∞ m=1 satisfies, for x, y ∈ X, x ∼∗SAO y iff there exists P ∈ S such that P x ∼∗O y; x ∗SAO y iff there exist P , Q ∈ S such that P x ∗O Qy. Proof. This result follows from the proof of of Kamaga and Kojima (2008b, Lemma 1) by noting that their properties P1, P2 and P3 (Kamaga and Kojima, 2008b, p. 16) are satisfied by a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs (note in particular Lemmas 1 and 3(i) of the present paper). Proof of Proposition 5.

Part I: If % extends %∗2 and satisfies SA and

WPC1, then %∗SAO is a subrelation of %. Consider an arbitrary pair x, y ∈ X. By Lemma 5, if x ∼∗SAO y, then there exists P ∈ S such that P x ∼∗O y. By ˜ = P x, this implies that there exists m ∈ N such that x ˜ N (n) ∼∗n yN (n) for writing x all n ≥ m. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and, by Proposition 2, satisfies WIC, ˜ ∼ y. Furthermore, x ∼ x ˜ since % satisfies SA. By transitivity, x ∼ y. x By Lemma 5, if x ∗SAO y, then there exist P , Q ∈ S such that P x ∗O Qy. ˜ = P x and y ˜ = Qy. By Proposition 3, x ˜ y ˜ since % extends %∗n for all Write x ˜ and y ˜ ∼ y since % satisfies SA. n ∈ N and satisfies WPC1. Furthermore, x ∼ x By transitivity, x  y. 15

Part II: If %∗SAO is a subrelation of %, then % extends %∗2 and satisfies SA and WSPC. We omit the straightforward proof of the result that % extends %∗2 . To show that % satisfies SA, assume that there exists P ∈ S such that P x = y. By Lemma 5, x ∼∗SAO y since %∗O is reflexive and x ∼ y since %∗SAO is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition SA. To show that % satisfies WSPC, assume that there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y for all n ≥ m. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) ˜ = P x and y ˜ = P y satisfy for all n ≥ m. Let P ∈ S have the property that x x ˜1 − y˜1 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜km − y˜km , while, for all n > m, x ˜k(n−1)+1 − y˜k(n−1)+1 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜kn − y˜kn . It now follows from the argument used in the proof of Lemma 4 that ˜ , (ii) by ˜ ∗O y ˜ N (n) for all n ∈ N. Hence, (i) by the definition of ∗O , x ˜ N (n) ∗n y x Lemma 5, x ∗SAO y and, finally, (iii) x  y since %∗SAO is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition WSPC. Since WSPC implies WPC1, parts I and II prove the proposition. Proposition 6 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. Then an SWR % extends %∗2 and satisfies WSIC1 and WPC1 iff %∗SO is a subrelation of %. Proof. Part I: If % extends %∗2 and satisfies WSIC1 and WPC1, then %∗SO is a subrelation of %. Consider an arbitrary pair x, y ∈ X. If x ∼∗SO y, then there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) ∼∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Set ` = km. Then xN (`n) ∼∗`n yN (`n) for all n ∈ N. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and satisfies WSIC1, x ∼ y. If x ∗SO y, then there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) for all ˜ = P x and y ˜ = P y satisfy x n ≥ m. Let P ∈ S have the property that x ˜1 − y˜1 ≥ ··· ≥ x ˜km − y˜km , while, for all n > m, x ˜k(n−1)+1 − y˜k(n−1)+1 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜kn − y˜kn . It ˜ N (n) ∗n y ˜ N (n) now follows from the argument used in the proof of Lemma 4 that x 16

˜  y ˜. for all n ∈ N. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and satisfies WPC1, x ˜ and y ˜ ∼ y since % satisfies WSIC. By transitivity, x  y. Furthermore, x ∼ x Part II: If %∗SO is a subrelation of %, then % extends %∗2 and satisfies WSIC and WSPC. We omit the straightforward proof of the result that % extends %∗2 . To show that % satisfies WSIC, assume that there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) ∼ y for all n ≥ m, then x ∼ y. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that xN (kn) ∼∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Hence, by the definition of %SO , x ∼∗SO y, and x ∼ y since %∗SO is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition WSIC. To show that % satisfies WSPC, assume that there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y for all n ≥ m. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Hence, by the definition of ∗SO , x ∗SO y, and x  y since %∗SO is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition WSPC. Since WSIC implies WSIC1 and WSPC implies WPC1, parts I and II prove the proposition. Proposition 7 Let {%∗m }∞ m=1 be a proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs. Then an SWR % extends %∗2 and satisfies WSIC and SSPC1 iff %∗SC is a subrelation of %. Proof. Part I: If % extends %∗2 and satisfies WSIC1 and SSPC1, then %∗SC is a subrelation of %. Consider an arbitrary pair x, y ∈ X. If x ∼∗SC y, then there exists k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) ∼∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Set ` = km. Then xN (`n) ∼∗`n yN (`n) for all n ∈ N. Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and satisfies WSIC1, x ∼ y. If x ∗SC y, then (i) there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) %∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m, and (ii) for all k, m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) . Set ` = km. Then xN (`n) %∗`n yN (`n) for all n ∈ N, and (ii) for all k, m ∈ N, there 17

exists n ≥ m such that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) . Since % extends %∗n for all n ∈ N and satisfies SSPC1, x  y. Part II: If %∗SC is a subrelation of %, then % extends %∗2 and satisfies WSIC and SSPC. We omit the straightforward proof of the result that % extends %∗2 . To show that % satisfies WSIC, assume that there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) ∼ y for all n ≥ m, then x ∼ y. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that xN (kn) ∼∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Hence, by the definition of %SC , x ∼∗SC y, and x ∼ y since %∗SC is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition WSIC. To show that % satisfies SSPC, assume that there exist k, m ∈ N such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) ) % y for all n ≥ m, and for all k, m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that (xN (kn) , yN\N (kn) )  y. Since % extends %∗2 and {%∗m }∞ m=1 is a proliferating sequence of SWOs, it follows from Lemma 2 that there exist k, m ∈ N such that xN (kn) %∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m, and for all k, m ∈ N, there exists n ≥ m such that xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) . Hence, by the definition of %∗SC , x ∗SC y, and x  y since %∗SC is a subrelation of %. This shows that % satisfies condition SSPC. Since WSIC implies WSIC1 and SSPC implies SSPC1, parts I and II prove the proposition. Our results are summarized in the following figure, where − signifies that no SWR satisfying the corresponding axioms exists, while + signifies that an SWR satisfying the corresponding axioms exists but is not analyzed here.3 The underlined combinations are axiomatizations applying a set of weakest axioms.

3

The non-existence results are reported in Kamaga and Kojima (2008b). A working paper

version of Kamaga and Kojima (2008b) analyzes the SWR satisfying WSPC1/WSPC only.

18

WPC1 WPC WSPC1 WSPC SSPC1 SSPC SPC1 SPC ∅

%∗O

%∗O

+

+

+

+

%∗C

%∗C

WIC

%∗O

%∗O

+

+

+

+

%∗C

%∗C

%∗SAO

%∗SAO

%∗SAO

%∗SAO

+

+





WSIC1 %∗SO

%∗SO

%∗SO

%∗SO

%∗SC

%∗SC





%∗SO

%∗SO

%∗SO

%∗SO

%∗SC

%∗SC





SA

WSIC

6

Concluding remarks

In the present paper we have provided axiomatizations that are weaker than those found in the literature of overtaking and catching up criteria, in a generalized setting where we do not have to discuss which finite-dimensional SWO is extended to the infinite-dimensional case. Compared to Asheim and Tungodden (2004) we weaken WPC to WPC1 in our characterization of the generalized overtaking criterion %∗O and SPC to SPC1 in our characterization of the generalized overtaking criterion %∗C . Compared to Basu and Mitra (2007) we in addition remove WIC in our axiomatizations of these criteria, as this axiom is not needed. Compared to Kamaga and Kojima (2008b) we weaken WPC to WPC1 and remove WIC in our characterization of the generalized fixed-step anonymous overtaking criterion %∗SAO and weaken WSPC1 to WPC1 in our characterization of the generalized fixed-step overtaking criterion %∗SO . Our axiomatization of the generalized fixed-step catching-up criterion, %∗SC , is new. For the purpose of applying the axiomatization of the present paper to discuss the relationships between the five different generalized criteria we have considered, adopt the following notation. For any generalized criterion R (where R = O, C, SAO, SO or SC) and any proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 ,

19

write I(R, ∗) := {(x, y) ∈ X2 | x ∼∗R y} , P (R, ∗) := {(x, y) ∈ X2 | x ∗R y} . for the symmetric and asymmetric parts of the criterion. It follows directly from Propositions 3–7 and the logical relationships between the axioms that, for any proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 , I(O, ∗) ⊆ I(C, ∗) , I(O, ∗) ⊆ I(SAO, ∗) ⊆ I(SO, ∗) ⊆ I(SC, ∗) , P (O, ∗) ⊆ P (C, ∗) , P (O, ∗) ⊆ P (SAO, ∗) ⊆ P (SO, ∗) ⊆ P (SC, ∗) . Furthermore, Definitions 2 and 3 imply that I(O, ∗) = I(C, ∗) and Definitions 5 and 6 imply that I(SO, ∗) = I(SC, ∗).4 Finally, Definitions 4 and 5 imply that P (SAO, ∗) = P (SO, ∗), as pointed out by Kamaga and Kojima (2008b, Proposition 3).5 However, as the following examples demonstrate, all other inclusions are strict. Consider the following six utility streams:

4

x

:

1

0

1

0

1

0

...

1

0

...

y

:

0

1

0

1

0

1

...

0

1

...

z

:

1 2

1 2

1 2

1 2

1 2

1 2

...

1 2

1 2

...

To see that I(SO, ∗) ⊇ I(SC, ∗), assume that x ∼∗SC y. I.e., there exist k0 , m0 , k00 , m00 ∈ N such

that xN (k0 n) %∗k0 n yN (k0 n) for all n ≥ m0 and xN (k0 n) -∗k00 n yN (k00 n) for all n ≥ m00 . Set k = k0 · k00 and m = max{m0 , m00 }. Then xN (kn) ∼∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m, showing that x ∼∗SO y. 5

To see that P (SAO, ∗) ⊇ P (SO, ∗), assume that x ∗SO y. I.e., there exist k, m ∈ N such that

˜ = P x and y ˜ = P y satisfy xN (kn) ∗kn yN (kn) for all n ≥ m. Let P ∈ S have the property that x x ˜1 − y˜1 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜km − y˜km , while, for all n > m, x ˜k(n−1)+1 − y˜k(n−1)+1 ≥ · · · ≥ x ˜kn − y˜kn . It now ˜ N (n) ∗n y ˜ N (n) for all n ∈ N. Hence, follows from the argument used in the proof of Lemma 4 that x ˜ ∗O y ˜ , and by Lemma 5, x ∗SAO y. by the definition of ∗O , x

20

(0, x)

:

0

1

0

1

0

1

...

0

1

...

(0, y)

:

0

0

1

0

1

0

...

1

0

...

( 21 , y)

:

1 2

0

1

0

1

0

...

1

0

... ,

and four more, u, v, u0 , v0 ∈ X, defined as follows:    1 if m = n2 and n ∈ N odd , um =   0 otherwise.    1 if m = n2 and n ∈ N even , vm =   0 otherwise.

u0m =

0 vm =

    1     1

2       0    1   2   

1       0

if m = 2n2 and n ∈ N odd , if m = 2n2 and n ∈ N even , otherwise. if m = 2n2 − 1 and n ∈ N odd , if m = 2n2 − 1 and n ∈ N even , otherwise.

We first show that the remaining inclusions between the indifference sets are strict. By Definition 2, it follows that (x, y) ∈ / I(O, ∗) = I(C, ∗) for any proliferating ∗ sequence of Paretian SWOs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 . On the other hand, as %SAO satisfies axiom

SA, (x, y) ∈ I(SAO, ∗). By Lemma 5, it follows that (x, z) ∈ / I(SAO, ∗) for any proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 . However, as pointed out by Kamaga and Kojima (2008b), for the special case of proliferating sequence of ∞ utilitarian SWOs, {%U m }m=1 , Definition 5 implies that (x, z) ∈ I(SO, U ) = I(SC, U ).

We then show that the remaining inclusions between the preference sets are strict. By Definition 2, it follows that neither ((0, x), (0, y)) nor ((0, x), ( 12 , y)) is an element of P (O, ∗) for any proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 , 21

while they are both elements of P (SAO, ∗), as %∗SAO satisfies axiom SA and the proliferating sequence of SWOs is Paretian. Definition 3 implies that, of these, ((0, x), (0, y)) ∈ P (C, ∗), while ((0, x), ( 21 , y)) ∈ / P (C, ∗). By Definition 5, it follows that neither (u, v) nor (u0 , v0 ) is an element of P (SO, ∗) for any proliferating sequence of Paretian SWOs, {%∗m }∞ m=1 , while they are both elements of P (SC, ∗). Definition 3 implies that, of these, (u, v) ∈ P (C, ∗), while (u0 , v0 ) ∈ / P (C, ∗). Finally, as we have seen, (x, y) ∈ I(SAO, ∗) ⊆ I(SO, ∗) = I(SC, ∗) and thus, (x, y) ∈ / P (SC, ∗), while Definition 3 implies that (x, y) ∈ P (C, ∗). The observation that (x, y) ∈ I(SAO, ∗) ⊆ I(SO, ∗) = I(SC, ∗), while ((0, x), (0, y)) ∈ P (SAO, ∗) = P (SO, ∗) ⊆ P (SC, ∗) illustrates the result that axiom SA contradicts Koopmans’s (1960) Stationarity axiom (in the sense that preference over future utilities should be independent of present utility) for any Paretian SWR.6 This questions the desirability of achieving increased comparability by imposing Fixedstep anonymity. On the other hand, relying on the overtaking and catching-up criteria considered in the present paper amounts to an increased sensitivity to the order in which utilities appear, which might also be less compelling. In a related paper (Asheim, d’Aspremont and Banerjee, 2008), we discuss how to construct SWRs to which Basu and Mitra’s (2007) and Bossert, Sprumont and Suzumura’s (2007) criteria are subrelations without compromising Stationarity and without introducing increased sensitivity to the sequencing of utilities.

6

Mitra (2007) discusses the problem of combining the Stationarity axiom with any kind of

extended anonymity.

22

References Asheim, G.B., d’Aspremont, C., and Banerjee, K. (2008), Generalized time-invariant overtaking. Mimeo, University of Oslo. Asheim, G.B. and Tungodden, B. (2004), Resolving distributional conflicts between generations, Economic Theory 24, 221–230. d’Aspremont, C. (2007), Formal welfarism and intergenerational equity. In: J. Roemer and K. Suzumura (eds.), Intergenerational Equity and Sustainability, Palgrave-Macmillan, Basingstoke, pp. 113–130. d’Aspremont, C. and Gevers, L. (1977), Equity and the informational basis for social choice. Review of Economic Studies 44, 199–208. Atsumi, H. (1965), Neoclassical growth and the efficient program of capital accumulation. Review of Economic Studies 32, 127–136. Banerjee, K. (2006), On the extension of the utilitarian and Suppes-Sen social welfare relations to infinite utility streams. Social Choice and Welfare 27, 327–339. Basu, K. and Mitra, T. (2007), Utilitarianism for infinite utility streams: A new welfare criterion and its axiomatic characterization. Journal of Economic Theory 133, 350–373. Bossert, W., Sprumont, Y., and Suzumura, K. (2007), Ordering infinite utility streams. Journal of Economic Theory 135, 579–589. Fleurbaey, M. and Michel, P. (2003), Intertemporal equity and the extension of the Ramsey criterion. Journal of Mathematical Economics 39, 777–802. Kamaga, K. and Kojima, T. (2008a), Q-anonymous social welfare relations on infinite utility streams. Mimeo, Waseda University. Kamaga, K. and Kojima, T. (2008b), On the leximin and utilitarian overtaking criteria with extended anonymity. Mimeo, Waseda University.

23

Koopmans, T.C. (1960), Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica 28, 287– 309. Lauwers, L. (1993), Equity among infinitely many generations. Mimeo, K.U.Leuven. Lauwers, L. (1997a), Rawlsian Equity and Generalized Utilitarianism with an Infinite Population, Economic Theory 9, 143-150. Lauwers, L. (1997b), Infinite utility: Insisting on strong monotonicity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75, 222–233. Lauwers, L. (2007), Ordering infinite utility streams comes at the cost of a non-Ramsey set. Mimeo, K.U.Leuven. Liedekerke, L. and Lauwers, L. (1997), Sacrificing the Patrol: Utilitarianism, Future Generations and Infinity, Economics and Philosophy 13, 159–174. Mitra, T. (2007), Stationary Paretian social welfare quasi-orderings and intergenerational equity. Mimeo, Cornell University. Mitra, T. and Basu, K. (2007), On the Existence of Paretian Social Welfare Relations for Infinite Utility Streams with Extended Anonymity. In: J. Roemer and K. Suzumura (eds.), Intergenerational Equity and Sustainability, Palgrave-Macmillan, Basingstoke. Sakai, T. (2008), Intergenerational equity and an explicit construction of welfare criteria. Mimeo, Yokohama National University. Sen, A. (1970), Collective Choice and Social Welfare, Holden-Day, San Francisco. Suppes, P. (1966), Some formal models of the grading principle, Synthese 6, 284–306. Zame, W. (2007), Can intergnerational equity be operationalized? Theoretical Economics 2, 187–202. von Weizs¨ acker, C. C. (1965), Existence of optimal program of accumulation for an infinite time horizon. Review of Economic Studies 32, 85–104.

24

Fixed-step anonymous overtaking and catching-up

Jan 20, 2009 - finite permutation π : {1,...,m}→{1,...,m} such that xiπ(k) = ujk and yiπ(k) = vjk for all k ∈ {1,...,m}, then xM ≿M yM if and only if uN ≿N vN . By satisfying m-I, ≿M depends only on ...... Lauwers, L. (1997a), Rawlsian Equity and Generalized Utilitarianism with an Infinite Pop- ulation, Economic Theory 9, 143-150.

247KB Sizes 3 Downloads 137 Views

Recommend Documents

Generalized time-invariant overtaking
Oct 29, 2008 - ... University of Oslo, P.O. Box 1095 Blindern, N-0317 Oslo, Norway. (e-mail: [email protected]). ‡CORE, Université catholique de Louvain, 34, Voie du Roman Pays, B-1348 Louvain-la-Neuve,. Belgium (e-mail: [email protected]

VANET's Mobility Models and Overtaking: An Overview
Email: [email protected], [email protected]. Abstract—The most important feature of Vehicular Ad hoc. Networks (VANETs) is the high mobility of ...

pdf-1447\overeaters-anonymous-from-overeaters-anonymous ...
pdf-1447\overeaters-anonymous-from-overeaters-anonymous-incorporated.pdf. pdf-1447\overeaters-anonymous-from-overeaters-anonymous-incorporated.pdf.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - bandwidth being offered by network carriers, not only data but also voice, audio and ... vices and associated tools, such as chat rooms, email and. Web publishing. ...... e.g., during the connection, via monitoring the transaction.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 27, 2008 - charges participant C a much loWer price for the ?shing advice. Moreover ..... tion (e.g., phone number, IP address, domain name, Web.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - DELIVERY OF REFERENCE .... known and increasingly diverse in direction, content and business ... Ebay, Yahoo, E*Trade and Amazon are.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 27, 2008 - 365/4917. 3,883,693 A * ..... The Internet is a collection of computer networks from ..... to support voice communication as voice over Internet pro.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 27, 2008 - CTI for Management Buyer's Guide, “Internet Phone. Release 4 ..... tends to have enhanced relevance in the commercial or pro fessional ...

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - question, inquiry or vieW (“posting”) at a selected Web site of the marketplace. ..... if the initiator attempts to make contact Within the expert's o?ice hours. As another ..... tion (e.g., phone number, IP address, domain name, W

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - By comparison, in circuit-switched networks, the call control functionality and ... In addition to hardware, software, protocols and infrastructure ...

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - 5,818,836 A * 10/1998 DuVal . ... 6,801,952 B2 10/2004 BelZile. 6,876,734 B1 ...... laptop personal computers, as Internet appliances, and as.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - 9/1999 D Anna.) et a1' ..... In addition to hardware, software, protocols and ...... codes, connect criteria based on contact codes, and/or ana.

Anonymous Donation.pdf
Apr 26, 2017 - TR/25225 and the assessee is also registered with Charity ... following information:- “a) Copy of letters ... Displaying Anonymous Donation.pdf.

Apparatus, methods and systems for anonymous communication
Aug 28, 2008 - Appl. No. 12/199,647; mailing date Apr. 13,2010; 13 pages. The '647 and '645 .... Accordingly, these networks enhance the ability of service providers to deploy new ... business model. Ebay, Yahoo, E*Trade and Amazon are.

Narcotics Anonymous -
(707) 324-4062 ext. 807. Group Support Forum .... 6:30 Sonoma (A-B-Y) “Living Clean Group”. Hanna Boys .... 2:00 Cotati (B-Q) “Freedom Friday”. Church of the ...

Anonymous investor.pdf
Because of the amount of data available to today's investors, information edge doesn't. exist anymore. The edge now comes from gut feel, and whose art of stock ...

Anonymous Rituals
Dec 10, 2009 - Email: [email protected]. ... Email: [email protected]. 1 .... We theorize that a key good provided by churches is mutual support.5 ...

Anonymous Resume.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. Anonymous ...

Anonymous threatens to expose the FBI and other government ...
government and police departments throughout the world including the United. States. ... the over 5,000 Pentagon employees for their purchasing and downloading of ... to expose the FBI and other government agencies for their alleged set.pdf.