The Journal of Symbolic Logic Volume 00, Number 0, XXX 0000

INCREASING ä 12 AND NAMBA-STYLE FORCING

ˇ RICHARD KETCHERSID, PAUL LARSON† , AND JINDRICH ZAPLETAL‡

Abstract. We isolate a forcing which increases the value of ä 12 while preserving ù1 under the assumption that there is a precipitous ideal on ù1 and a measurable cardinal.

§1. Introduction. The problem of comparison between ordinals defined in descriptive set theory such as ä 1n , n ∈ ù and cardinals such as ℵn , n ∈ ù has haunted set theorists for decades. In this paper, we want to make a humble comment on the comparison between ä 12 and ù2 . Hugh Woodin showed [6] that if the nonstationary ideal on ù1 is saturated and there is a measurable cardinal then ä 12 = ℵ2 . Thus the iterations for making the nonstationary ideal saturated must add new reals, and they must increase ä 12 . It is a little bit of a mystery how this happens, since the new reals must be born at limit stages of the iteration and no one has been able to construct a forcing increasing the ordinal ä 12 explicitly. The paper [7] shed some light on this problem; it produced a single step Namba type forcing which can increase ä 12 in the right circumstances. In this paper we clean up and optimize the construction and prove: Theorem 1.1. Suppose that there is a normal precipitous ideal on ù1 and a measurable cardinal κ. For every ordinal ë ∈ κ there is an ℵ1 preserving poset forcing ä 12 > ë. An important disclaimer: this result cannot be immediately used to iterate and obtain a model where ä 12 = ℵ2 from optimal large cardinal hypotheses. The forcing obtained increases ä 12 once, to a value less than ù2 . If the reader wishes to iterate the construction in order to obtain a model where ä 12 = ù2 , he will encounter the difficult problem of forcing a precipitous ideal on ù1 by an ℵ1 -preserving poset. Forcing ä 12 = ℵ2 may be possible with some other type of accumulation of partial orders obtained in this paper. The notation in this paper is standard and follows [2]. After the paper was written we learned that a related construction was discovered by Jensen [4]: a Namba-type Received October 31, 2006. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. † Partially supported by DMS NSF grant 0401603 ‡ Partially supported by GA CR ˇ grant 201-03-0933 and DMS NSF grant 0300201. c 0000, Association for Symbolic Logic

0022-4812/00/0000-0000/$00.00

1

2

ˇ RICHARD KETCHERSID, PAUL LARSON, AND JINDRICH ZAPLETAL

forcing in the model L[U ] with one measurable cardinal introducing a mouse which iterates to any length given beforehand. §2. Generic ultrapowers, iterations, and ä 12 . In order to prepare the ground for the forcing construction, we need to restate several basic definitions and claims regarding the generic ultrapowers and their iterations. Definition 2.1. [3] Suppose that J is a ó-ideal on ù1 . If G ⊂ P (ù1 ) \ J is a generic filter, then we consider the generic ultrapower j : V → N modulo the filter G, in which only the ground model functions are used. If the model N is wellfounded, it is identified with its transitive collapse, and the ideal J is called precipitous. The following definitions and facts have been isolated in [6]. Definition 2.2. [6] Suppose that M is a countable transitive model, and M |= “J is a precipitous ideal”. An iteration of length â ≤ ù1 of the model M is a sequence Mα : α ≤ â of models together with commuting system of elementary embeddings; successor stages are obtained through a generic ultrapower, and limit stages through a direct limit. A model is iterable if all of its iterands are wellfounded. Definition 2.3. [1] Suppose J is a precipitous ideal on ù1 . An elementary submodel M of a large structure with j ∈ M is selfgeneric if for every maximal antichain A ⊂ P (ù1 ) \ J in the model M there is a set B ∈ A ∩ M such that M ∩ ù1 ∈ B. In other words, the filter {B ∈ M ∩ P (ù1 ) \ J : M ∩ ù1 ∈ B} is an M -generic filter. Note that if M is a selfgeneric submodel, N is the Skolem hull of M ∪ {M ∩ ù1 }, and j : M¯ → N¯ is the elementary embedding between the transitive collapses induced by id : M → N , then j is a generic ultrapower of the model M by the genric filter identified in the above definition. The key observation is that selfgeneric models are fairly frequent: Proposition 2.4. Suppose that J is a precipitous ideal on ù1 and ì > 2ℵ1 is a regular cardinal. The set of countable selfgeneric elementary submodels of Hì is stationary in [Hì ]ℵ0 . Proof. Suppose that f : Hì<ù → Hì is a function; we must find a selfgeneric submodel of Hì closed under it. Let G ⊂ P (ù1 ) \ J be a generic filter and j : V → N be the associated generic ultrapower embedding into a transitive model. Note that j ′′ HìV is a selfgeneric submodel of j(Hì ) closed under the function j(f); it is not in general an element of the model N . Consider the tree T of all finite attempts to build a selfgeneric submodel of j(Hì ) closed under the function j(f). Then T ∈ N and the previous sentence shows that the tree T is illfounded in V [G]. Since the model N is transitive, it must be the case that the tree T is illfounded in N too, and so M |= there is a countable selfgeneric elementary submodel of j(Hì ) closed under the function j(f). An elementarity argument then yields a countable selfgeneric elementary submodel of the structure Hì closed under the function f in the ground model as desired. ⊣ Our approach to increasing ä 12 is in spirit the same as that of Woodin. We start with a ground model V with a precipitous ideal J on ù1 , a measurable cardinal κ,

INCREASING ä 12 AND NAMBA-STYLE FORCING

3

and an ordinal ë ∈ κ. Choose a regular cardinal ì between ë and κ. In the generic extension V [G], it will be the case that ù1V = ù1V [G] and κ is still measurable and moreover there is a countable elementary submodel M ≺ HìV such that • M is selfgeneric • M¯ is iterable • ë is a subset of one of the iterands of M¯ . In fact, it will be the case that writing Mα , α ∈ ù1 for the models obtained by transfinite inductive procedure M0 = M , Mα+1 = Skolem hull of Mα ∪ {Mα ∩ ù1 }, S and Mα = â∈α for limit ordinals α, and writing M¯ α for the respective transitive collapses, the models Mα are all selfgeneric, the models M¯ α , α ≤ ù1 constitute an S iteration of the model M¯ , and ë ⊂ α Mα . By Lemma 4.7 of [6], ä 12 must be larger than the cumulative hierarchy rank of the model M¯ ù1 , which by the third item is at least ë. Note that the model M cannot be an element of the ground model. It may seem that adding a model M such that all the models Mα , α ∈ ù1 are selfgeneric is an overly ambitious project. The forcing will in fact add a countable set {fn : n ∈ ù} ⊂ HìV such that every countable elementary submodel containing it as a subset is necessarily selfgeneric. It will also add a countable set {gn : n ∈ ù} ⊂ HìV S of functions from ù1<ù to ù such that ë = n rng(gn ). This will be achieved by a variation of the classical Namba construction by an ℵ1 -preserving forcing of size < κ. In the generic extension, use the measurability of κ to find an elementary submodel N of a large structure containing J, ì, κ as well as the functions fn , gn , n ∈ ù such that the ordertype of N ∩ κ is ù1 , and consider the transitive collapse N¯ of the model N ∩ V . It is iterable by Lemma 4.5 of [6]. This means that even the transitive collapse M¯ of the model M = N ∩ HìV is iterable, since it is a rank-initial segment of N¯ and every iteration of M¯ extends to an iteration of N¯ . Thus the model M is as desired, and this will complete the proof. §3. A class of Namba-like forcings. Definition 3.1. Suppose that X is a set and I is a collection of subsets of X closed under subsets, X ∈ / I . The forcing QI consists of all nonempty trees T ⊂ X <ù such that every node t ∈ T has an extension s ∈ T such that {x ∈ X : s a x ∈ T } ∈ / I. The ordering is that of inclusion. It is not difficult to see that the forcing QI adds a countable sequence of elements of the underlying set X . The only property of the generic sequence we will use is that it is not a subset of any ground model set in the collection I . The usual Namba forcing is subsumed in the above definition: just put X = ℵ2 and I = all subsets of ù2 of size ℵ1 . A small variation of the argument in [5] will show that whenever I is an < ℵ2 -complete ideal then the forcing QI preserves ℵ1 and if in addition CH holds then no new reals are added. We want to increase the ordinal ä 12 , so we must add new reals, and so we must consider weaker closure properties of the collection I . The following definition is critical. Definition 3.2. Suppose that J is an ideal on a set Y , X is a set, and I is a collection of subsets of X . We say that I is closed under J integration if for every J -positive set B ⊂ Y and every set D ⊂ B × X whose vertical sections are in I the R / D} ∈ J } ⊂ X is also in the collection I . set B D dJ = {x ∈ X : {y ∈ B : hy, xi ∈

4

ˇ RICHARD KETCHERSID, PAUL LARSON, AND JINDRICH ZAPLETAL

We will use this definition in the context of a precipitous ideal J on ù1 . In this case, the closure under J integration allows of an attractive reformulation: Proposition 3.3. Suppose that J is a precipitous ideal on ù1 and I is a collection of subsets of some set X closed under inclusion. Then I is closed under J -integration if and only if P (ù1 ) \ J forces that writing j : V → M for the generic ultrapower, the closure of I under J integration is equivalent to the statement that for every set A ⊂ X not in I , the set j ′′ A is not covered by any element of j(I ). Proof. For the left-to-right implication, assume that I is closed under J integration. Suppose that some condition forces that C˙ ∈ j(I ) is a set; strengthening this condition of necessary we can find a set B ∈ P (ù1 ) \ J and a function f : B → I such that B C˙ = j(f)(ùˇ 1 ).R Let D ⊂ B × X be defined by / I is a hα, xi ∈ D ↔ x ∈ f(α) andR observe that B D dJ ∈ I . Thus, if A ∈ / f(α)} ⊂ B set, it contains an element x ∈ / B D dJ , then the set B ′ = {α ∈ B : x ∈ ˇ 6⊂ C˙ . is J -positive and as a P (ù1 ) \ J condition it forces j(x) ∈ / C˙ and j(A) The opposite implication is similar. ⊣ The reader should note the similarity between the above definition and the Fubini properties of ideals on Polish spaces as defined in [8]. The basic property of the class of forcings we have just introduced is the following. Proposition 3.4. Suppose that J is a precipitous ideal on ù1 , X is a set, and I is a collection of subsets of the set X closed under J integration. Then the forcing QI preserves ℵ1 . Proof. Suppose that T f˙ : ùˇ → ùˇ 1 is a function. A usual fusion argument provides for a tree S ⊂ T in the poset QI such that for every node t ∈ S on the ˙ n) n-th splitting level the condition S ↾ t decides the value of the ordinal f( ˇ to be some definite ordinal g(t) ∈ ù1 . Here, S ↾ t is the tree of all nodes of the tree S inclusion-compatible with t. To prove the theorem, it is necessary to find a tree U ⊂ S and an ordinal α ∈ ù1 such that the range g ′′ U is a subset of α. For every ordinal α ∈ ù1 consider a game Gα between Players I and II in which the two players alternate for infinitely many rounds indexed by n ∈ ù, Player I playing nodes tn ∈ T on the n-th splitting level of the tree T and Player II answering with a set An ∈ I . Player I is required to play so that t0 ⊂ t1 ⊂ . . . and the first element on the sequence tn+1 \ tn is not in the set An . He wins if the ordinals g(tn ), n ∈ ù are all smaller than α. It is clear that these games are closed for Player I and therefore determined. Note that if Player I has a winning strategy ó in the game Gα for some ordinal α ∈ ù1 , then the collection of all nodes which can arise as the answers of strategy ó to some play by Player II forms a tree U in QI and g ′′ U ⊂ α. Thus the following claim will complete the proof of the theorem. Claim 3.5. There is an ordinal α ∈ ù1 such that Player I has a winning strategy in the game Gα . Assume for contradiction that Player II has a winning strategy óα for every ordinal α ∈ ù1 . Let M ≺ Hκ be a selfgeneric countable elementary submodel of some large structure containing the sequence of these strategies as well as X , I , J . Let â = M ∩ ù1 . We will find a legal counterplay against the strategy óâ in which Player I uses only moves from the model M . It is clear that in such a counterplay,

INCREASING ä 12 AND NAMBA-STYLE FORCING

5

the ordinals g(tn ), n ∈ ù stay below â. Therefore Player I will win this play, and that will be the desired contradiction. The construction of the counterplay proceeds by induction. Build nodes tn , n ∈ ù of the tree S as well as subsets Bn , n ∈ ù of ù1 so that • B0 ⊃ B1 ⊃ . . . are all J -positive sets in the model M such that â ∈ Bn for every number n • t0 ⊂ t1 ⊂ · · · ⊂ tn are all in the model M and they form a legal finite counterplay against all strategies óα , α ∈ Bn , in particular, against the strategy óâ . Suppose that the node tn ∈ S ∩ M and the set Bn have been found. Consider the set D = {hα, xi : α ∈ Bn , x ∈ óα (tn )} ⊂ B × X . Its vertical R sections are sets in the collection I , and by the assumptions so are the integrals C D dJ for all J -positive sets C ⊂ Bn . Since the node tn ∈ S has more than I many immediate successors, it follows that the set A = {C ⊂ Bn : C ∈ / J and ∃x ∈ X ∀α ∈ C tna x ∈ S ∧ x ∈ / óα (tn )} is dense in P (ù1 ) \ J below the set Bn . This set is also in the model M and by the selfgenericity there is a point x ∈ X ∩ M such that tna x ∈ S and the set Sn+1 = {α ∈ Bn : x ∈ / óα (tn )} is in the set A ∩ M and contains the ordinal â. The node tn+1 ⊃ tn is then just any node at n + 1-st splitting level extending tna x. Clearly, tn+1 ∈ M by the elementarity of the model M . This concludes the inductive construction and the proof. ⊣ As the last remark in this section, the class of sets I closed under J -integration is itself closed on various operations, and this leads to simple operations on the partial orders of the form QI . We will use the following operation. If X0 , X1 are disjoint sets and I0 ⊂ P (X0 ) and I1 ⊂ P (X1 ) are sets closed under subsets and J integration, then also the set K ⊂ P (X0 ∪X1 ) defined by A ∈ K if either A∩X0 ∈ I0 or A ∩ X1 ∈ I1 is closed under subsets and J -integration. It is easy to see that the forcing QK adds an ù sequence of elements of X0 ∪ X1 which cofinally often visits both sets and its intersection with X0 or X1 is not a subset of any ground model set in I0 or I1 respectively. §4. Wrapping up. Fix a normal precipitous ideal J on ù1 , a measurable cardinal κ, and an ordinal ë < κ. Theorem 1.1 is now proved through identification of several interesting collections of sets closed under J -integration. This does not refer to the precipitousness of the ó-ideal J anymore. Definition 4.1. X0 is the set of all functions from ù1<ù to ë. I0 ⊂ P (X0 ) is the closure of the set of its generators under subset and J -integration, where the generators of I0 are the sets Aα = {g ∈ X0 : α ∈ / rng(g)} for α ∈ ë. The obvious intention behind the definition is that if {gn : n ∈ ù} S ⊂ X0 is a set of functions which is not covered by any element of the set I0 then n rng(gn ) = ë. With the previous section in mind, we must prove that X0 ∈ / I0 . Unraveling the definitions, it is clear that it is just necessary to prove that whenever n is a natural number, S ⊂ ù1n is a J n -positive set,R and D ⊂ S × X0 is a set whose vertical sections are I0 -generators, then the integral S D dJ n is not equal to X0 . Here J n is the usual n-fold Fubini power of the ideal J . Let g : ù1n → ë be a function such that for every n-tuple â~ ∈ S, the vertical section Dâ~ is just the generator Ag(â) ~ . Then clearly R R S n n g∈ / â~∈S Dâ~ , in particular g ∈ / S D dJ and S D dJ 6= X0 .

6

ˇ RICHARD KETCHERSID, PAUL LARSON, AND JINDRICH ZAPLETAL

Definition 4.2. X1 is the set of all functions with domain ù1<ù × A and range a subset of ù1 × P (ù1 ). Here A is the set of all maximal antichains in the forcing P (ù1 ) \ J . The set I1 is the closure of the set of its generators under subset and J -integration, where the generators of I1 are the sets of the form Aα,Z = {f ∈ X1 : ~ Z)(0) ∈ α and f(â, ~ Z)(1) is not a set in Z for every finite sequence â~ ∈ α <ù , f(â, containing α}, where α ∈ ù1 and Z ∈ A are arbitrary. The obvious intention behind this definition is that whenever {fn : n ∈ ù} is a countable subset of X1 which is not covered by any element of the set I1 then every countable elementary submodel M ≺ Hì containing all these functions must be self-generic: whenever Z ∈ M is a maximal antichain in P (ù1 ) \ J , writing α = M ∩ ù1 , there must be a number n such that fn ∈ / Aα,Z . Perusing the definition of the set Aα,Z and noting that M is closed under the function fn , we conclude that it must be the case that for some finite sequence â~ ∈ α <ù the value ~ Z) ∈ M must be a set in Z containing the ordinal α. Since the maximal fn (â, antichain Z was arbitrary, this shows that M is self-generic as required. We must prove that X1 ∈ / I1 . This is a rather elementary matter, nevertheless it is somewhat more complicated than the 0 subscript case. Unraveling the definitions, it is clear that it is just necessary to prove that whenever n is a natural number, S ⊂ ù1n is a J n -positive set, andR D ⊂ S × X0 is a set whose vertical sections are I1 -generators, then the integral S D dJ n is not equal to X1 . Here J n is the usual n-fold Fubini power of the ideal J . Fix then n ∈ ù, a J n -positive set S ⊂ ù1n , and the set D ⊂ S × X1 ; we must find a function f ∈ X1 and a Jn -positive set U ⊂ S ~ fi ∈ such that ∀â~ ∈ U hâ, / D. For every sequence â~ ∈ S choose a countable ordinal ~ ~ ⊂ P (ù1 ) \ J such that D ~ = A ~ ~ . Use α(â) and a maximal antichain Z(â) â α(â),Z(â) standard normality arguments to find numbers m, k ≤ n and a J n -positive set T ⊂ S consisting of increasing sequences such that ~ depends only on â~ ↾ m and α(â) ~ ≥ • for a sequence â~ ∈ T , the value of α(â) ~ â(m − 1) ~ depends only on â~ ↾ k and the partial map ð with domain • the value of Z(â) k ~ = ð(â~ ↾ k) whenever â~ ∈ T , is countable-to-one. ù , defined by Z(â) 1

There are now several cases. ~ > â(m ~ − 1). Here, consider • There is a J n -positive set U ⊂ T such that α(â) ~ for every sequence â~ ∈ U the function f ∈ X1 such that f(â~ ↾ m, Z) = S α(â) Dâ~ as required: for every and every maximal antichain Z. Clearly, f ∈ / â∈U ~ ~ = f(â~ ↾ m, Z(â~ ))(0) and so the sequence â~ ∈ U , it is the case that α(â) ~ ordinal α(â) does not have the required closure property with respect to f. • The first case fails and k ≥ m. Here, define the map f ∈ X1 by f(0, Z)(0) = ~ − 1) : â~ ∈ T and Z = Z(â)} ~ + 1 for every maximal antichain Z. The sup{â(k ~ = â(m ~ set U = {y ∈ T : α(â) − 1)} and the map f are as required: again, ~ ≤ â(k ~ − 1) < f(0, Z(â))(0) ~ for every sequence â ∈ U the ordinal α(â) does not have the required closure properties. • The first case fails and k < m. Define the function f ∈ X1 in the following way. For every sequence ~ã ∈ ù1m−1 , if the set W~ã = {α ∈ ù1 : ∃â~ ∈ T ~ãa α ⊂ â~ ~ is J -positive, let f(~ã, ð(~ã ↾ k)) to be some element of the and α = α(â)}

INCREASING ä 12 AND NAMBA-STYLE FORCING

7

maximal antichain ð(~ã ↾ k) with J -positive intersection with W~ã . The set ~ = â(m) ~ ~ U = {â~ ∈ T : α(â) and â(m) ∈ f(â~ ↾ (m − 1), ð(â~ ↾ k)} is then J n S ~ belongs to the set positive and f ∈ / â∈U Dâ~ as required: the ordinal α(â) ~ ~ ∈ Z(â). ~ f(â~ ↾ k, Z(â)) Thus X1 ∈ / I1 . To conclude the proof of Theorem 1.1, just form a collection K ⊂ P (X0 ∪ X1 ) as in the end of the previous section and force with the poset QK . Since K is closed under J -integration, the forcing preserves ℵ1 . It also adds sets {fn : n ∈ ù} ⊂ X1 and {gn : n ∈ ù} ⊂ X0 with the required properties, showing that in the generic extension, ä 12 > ë. REFERENCES

[1] Matthew Foreman, Menachem Magidor, and Saharon Shelah, Martin’s Maximum, saturated ideals, and non-regular ultrafilters I, Annals of Mathematics, vol. 127 (1988), pp. 1– 47. [2] Thomas Jech, Set theory, Academic Press, San Diego, 1978. [3] Thomas Jech, Menachem Magidor, William Mitchell, and Karel Prikry, Precipitous ideals, this Journal, vol. 45 (1980), pp. 1–8. [4] Ronald Jensen, Making cardinals ù-cofinal, handwritten notes, 1990s. [5] Kanji Namba, Independence proof of a distributive law in complete Boolean algebras, Commentarii Mathematici Universitatis Sancti Pauli, vol. 19 (1970), pp. 1–12. [6] Hugh Woodin, The axiom of determinacy, forcing axioms and the nonstationary ideal, Walter de Gruyter, New York, 1999. [7] Jindrich Zapletal, The nonstationary ideal and the other sigma-ideals on omega one, Transactions ˇ of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 352 (2000), pp. 3981–3993. [8] , Forcing idealized, Cambridge University Press, 2007, to appear. MIAMI UNIVERSITY MIAMI UNIVERSITY UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA

INCREASING 1 2 AND NAMBA-STYLE FORCING §1 ...

forcing in the model L[U] with one measurable cardinal introducing a mouse which iterates to any length given ..... MIAMI UNIVERSITY. UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA.

112KB Sizes 0 Downloads 34 Views

Recommend Documents

Krugman 1991 Cap 1 Increasing returnos and Economic Geography ...
Krugman 1991 Cap 1 Increasing returnos and Economic Geography.pdf. Krugman 1991 Cap 1 Increasing returnos and Economic Geography.pdf. Open. Extract.

ARITHMETICAL SACKS FORCING 1. introduction Two ...
Ann. of Math. (2) 64 (1956), 581–592. School of Mathematics and Computing Sciences, Victoria University of Wellington,. Wellington, New Zealand. E-mail address: [email protected]. Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, National Unive

Abraham and Isaac Genesis 22:1-19 1. Courageous Faith – vv.1-2 2 ...
Jun 18, 2017 - Wrestle with the statement: Faith is not “Can I?” it's “Will I?” If you couldn't, ... slow cookers. What kind of trial are you in right now that requires.

Page 1 / 2 Loading… Page 1 Page 2 of 2 ...
Sign in. Page. 1. /. 2. Loading… Page 1. Page 2 of 2. Eacb1567b148a94cb2dd5d612c7b769256279ca60_Q8633_R329927_D1856546.pdf. Eacb1567b148a94cb2dd5d612c7b769256279ca60_Q8633_R329927_D1856546.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displayi

Abraham and Isaac Genesis 22:1-19 1. Courageous Faith – vv.1-2 2 ...
Jun 18, 2017 - How could you sum up the meaning of this passage in your own words? Application: How does this passage challenge your understanding about who. God is and what he is like? Is there some attitude or belief you need to change? © Matthias

Abraham and Isaac Genesis 22:1-19 1. Courageous Faith – vv.1-2 2 ...
Jun 18, 2017 - If the statement little faith = little power and much faith = much power is true, how would your life ... find a greater harvest of truth! Context: Gen.

1 1 2 2 AABB 04/02/2009 1 PAGE: 1 UNCC SHANE ... - John-Tom.com
Feb 4, 2009 - .4375 x .4 Cast Iron. Piston. 1. 5 .125" Dowel. Wrist Pin. 1. 6 .75" sq. x .9" Steel cylinder. 1. 7. 2-56 x .2" Socket Head. 2-56. 12. 8 .75" sq. x .3" Al.

Page 1 1 " " ! $ $% % '' ' " # $ % ' /' 1 % 2 2 % % 2 55 7'8 %'% 9 : ' 5 ...
extremel elusive snow and the clouded Leopard. The para is also a Tiker Reserve under Pro ect Tiker. Velvadhar Blacakuca Sanctuar , Gu arat. Popularl anown as the home of the Indian Blaca Buca, has attracted worldwide attention for the successful con

Page 1 1 " " ! $ $% % '' ' " # $ % ' /' 1 % 2 2 % % 2 55 7'8 %'% 9 : ' 5 ...
extremel elusive snow and the clouded Leopard. The para is also a Tiker Reserve under Pro ect Tiker. Velvadhar Blacakuca Sanctuar , Gu arat. Popularl anown as the home of the Indian Blaca Buca, has attracted worldwide attention for the successful con

Time Is Money: Increasing Your Speed to Market 1 - Business ...
businesses the opportunity to dominate the market, even with ... this by establishing a protocol requiring that any and all ... entered or changed in one location, it.

Ohio UnsummitFlyer3+RegFormPRINT2018 (1) (2) (1)SR.pdf ...
Ensure the Contact Information section is completed with information you want to use in the program (organization name,. address, phone, website, etc.) Please list the name(s) that will be attending: 1.

binary.c 1/1 bmp.h 1/2 - CS50 CDN
4: * Computer Science 50. 5: * David J. Malan. 6: * ... 32: * The BITMAPFILEHEADER structure contains information about the type, size,. 33: * and layout of a file ...

dt u U x J + = 2 1 ) ( 2 1
b) Formulate the optional control problem in terms of Hamiltonian. 6. Derive the H J B equation in the continues time care. 7. Explain the method of getting Bode ...

o 1:2
and conforms With all FDA approved application protocols for the devices. ..... required to adhere to What the FDA de?nes as “Good Manu facturing Practices. ... ?rst 1,000 units call for a soldering station and Will be imple mented according to ...

Page# 1 / 2 - Groups
SUPERINTENDENT OF POLICE (CIVIL). 10100821. 10101546. 10202048. 10204206. 10205191. 10206119. 10207129. 10207940. 10209373. 10301825.

Σ2 Σ1
The solution of an autonomous dynamic system is denoted by z(t, z0) where z0 = z(t0,z0) is the initial state. We say that a function V : Rq → R≥0 is smooth if it is infinitely ..... Assume that there exists a virtual control τc := k(t, x), such

1 Using an AGCM to diagnose historical effective radiative forcing and ...
May 24, 2013 - It is currently most easily achieved using a global energy budget approach. 63 ... and solar constant representative of the period being simulated (Gates, 1992). The ...... 2008) changes in radiatively active constituents, such as ...

binary.c 1/1 bmp.h 1/2 - CS50 CDN
19: * Adapted from http://msdn.microsoft.com/en-us/library/cc230309(PROT.10).aspx. 20: * See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Stdint.h for more on stdint.h. 21: */. 22:.

Page# 1 / 2 - Groups
REGISTER NUMBERS. REGISTER NUMBERS: POST CODE : 1 – DEPUTY COLLECTORS. 10100515. 10101279. 10500269. 10607155. 11005824. 11503290.

froshims.html 1/2
41: Mower. 42: Pennypacker. 43: Stoughton. 44: Straus. 45: Thayer. 46: Weld ...

1/2 index.html 2/2 - CS50 CDN
20: . 21: CS50 Shuttle. 22: . 23: . 24:

froshims.html 1/2
Page 1. froshims.html. 1/2 lectures/2/src/. 1: 2: