Inequality and a Repeated Joint Project Olivier Dagnelie ´ ´ Instituto de Analisis Economico CSIC

AEA Meeting - January 3rd, 2009

Topic: Influence of share inequality on the scope for cooperation sustainability → δ

Novelty: Renegotiation-proof and coalition-proof solution for a prisoners’ dilemma with n players and continuous strategies

Results: I

in a specific model, negative effect of inequality on cooperation, efficiency

I

coexistence of one cooperating and one deviating coalition repetition of the game and outside options enlarge the scope for redistribution

I

Repeated PD : Renegotiation proofness C D

C 1,1 2,-1

D -1,2 0,0

Nash Reversion (1 − δ)π D + δπ N < π C ⇒ δ >

πD − πC 1 ⇒δ> D N π −π 2

Problem : both players suffer from the punishment ⇒ incentives to renegotiate.

Renegotiation Proof Solution πD −πC πC −πP P∗ −π P δXP > ππC −π P 1/P∗ 1/P

1 2 1 2

δXA >



δ>

π <π π 1/P ≥ π C

⇒ → →

δ> 1<2 2>1

Outline Introduction Repeated Joint Production with Shares Nash Reversion A Renegotiation-Proof and Coalition-Proof Equilibrium Redistribution and Cooperation Outside Option Conclusion

I

There exist many examples of voluntarily provided joint projects in the real world: collective action problems in management of environmental resources (forests, fisheries, irrigation schemes), financial lobbying, defense alliances, etc.

I

In static games, the first-best optimum is known not to be sustainable as nothing prevents agents from deviating. ⇒ If such a game is infinitely repeated, one can expect new (1st best) solutions to be sustainable. If there exists inequality between agents, Olson (1965) argued that this kind of projects work best when one single agent gets all the shares (concentration of all the incentives).

I

I

Olson’s result depends on unstated assumptions: - Nash behaviour - perfect substitutability of efforts - identical marginal costs - single interactions

Literature review:

I

Effect of inequality on efficiency is ambiguous (depending on the cost function) → Khwaja (2006), Barnerjee et al. (2001, 2006).

I

Tarui (2007), influence of inequality of productivity, access to markets and credit in a dynamic intergenerational game of common property resource use.

I

Bardhan & Singh (2005), influence of wealth inequality on cooperation sustained by Nash reversion in an infinitely repeated game.

I

Itaya & Yamada (2003), influence of income inequality on a repeated game of private provision of public goods (2 players).

I

Vasconcelos (2005), tacit collusion in quantity-setting supergames with asymmetric costs.

I

Joint project : voluntary contributions

I

Same discount factor for all agents

I

Output divided according to some given vector of shares (for instance: wealth inequality): P λ≡ [λ1 , λ2 , . . . , λn ] with i λi = 1 P eγ Collective action individual payoff: πi = λi j∈n ej − γλi i , with γ≥2

I

1

I

Cooperation level of effort: eiC = λiγ−1 2

Deviation level of effort: eiN = λiγ−1 ⇒ eiC > eiN (underprovision of the ’public good’)

Repeated Joint Production with Shares Lemma The agent who benefits most from deviating, relatively to one’s share, is always the one with the lowest share. Relatively, the poorest player is the one having the most to win. → ’Exploitation by the poor’

Repeated Joint Production with Shares Lemma The agent who benefits most from deviating, relatively to one’s share, is always the one with the lowest share. Relatively, the poorest player is the one having the most to win. → ’Exploitation by the poor’ I



If πiC < πiC , deviating from the cooperation effort is not profitable. ∗ For deviating to be interesting: πiC > πiC . If λi = n−1 , I I I

always true if nD = 1. if γ ≥ 2, true if nD < n+1 . 2 nD /n decreases with n

→ if too many deviations, the small surplus is to be divided among too many for deviating to remain profitable.

Nash Reversion





(1 − δN )πiC + δN πiN < πiC ⇒ δN >

πiC − πiC ∗ πiC − πiN

Nash Reversion





(1 − δN )πiC + δN πiN < πiC ⇒ δN > I

πiC − πiC ∗ πiC − πiN

δN < 1 ⇒ the bigger the difference πiC − πiN , the smaller δN and therefore the easier cooperation can be sustained. λi = n−1 ⇒ πiC > πiN

Proposition Introducing inequality among agents renders the condition to sustain cooperation with Nash reversion more difficult to fulfill.

Figure: Influence of the λ1 distribution on δN when γ = 3 and n = 3

A Renegotiation-Proof and Coalition-Proof Equilibrium → define R and P: efforts when punishing and being punished

Punishment scheme: As soon as a coalition deviates, the cooperative agents play a retaliation level of effort R until the deviators have undergone their punishment P.

A Renegotiation-Proof and Coalition-Proof Equilibrium → define R and P: efforts when punishing and being punished

Punishment scheme: As soon as a coalition deviates, the cooperative agents play a retaliation level of effort R until the deviators have undergone their punishment P.

Length of punishment: Trade-off between ex ante discouraging deviations and ex post encouraging deviations from the punishment (latter effect is dominating).

Lemma Aiming at the smallest discount factor compatible with a renegotiation-proof and coalition-proof punishment limits the length of the punishment phase to one period.

5 conditions for the equilibrium to be renegotiation-proof and coalition-proof:

2 conditions concerning the deviators I

Ex ante, the punishment must be such that deviations are deterred. (→ δXA )

I

Ex post, the punishment must be such that deviations from the punishment are deterred. (→ δXP )

2 conditions concerning the cooperators I

The payoff of the punishers must be greater when conforming than when deviating from punishing and then conforming, i.e. 1/P 1/P ∗ πi > πi . → gives R ≡ eiN .

I

For the equilibrium to be coalition-proof, no deviation should be 1/P ∗ 1/P ∗∗ credible, i.e. πi < πi . As no deviation of punishers is credible when the punished conform to their punishment, a fortiori, it is also the case when some punished refuse to undergo the penalty.

1 condition for renegotiation-proofness I

The payoff from punishing a deviating coalition must be greater or equal than the payoff from generalized cooperation, i.e. 1/P πi ≥ πiC . → gives P.

We want to get δ ≡ min max(δXA , δXP ) ∗

Comparing δXA and δXP is comparing π C − π C and (≤)π N − π P . I

if P = eiC , δ = δXA = δXP .

I

if P > eiC , we have to minimize P to get δ ⇒ P ≡ P .

I

if P < P, the punishment would not be RPCP.

I

if P < eiC , agents could alternate between deviating and being punished. ⇒ P ≡ max(eiC , P)

It means that, under an equalitarian distribution: n 2

I

P = eiC , when nD ≥

I

in the other cases, P = P

if γ ≥ 2

The condition to be fulfilled for cooperation to be sustainable is: πiC > πiN

Proposition As long as δXP < δ < 1, λi = n−1 and the game is infinitely repeated, it is possible to sustain cooperation with a renegotiation-proof and coalition-proof punishment.

Once we introduce inequality, the same rule applies.

Proposition After introducing inequality, the agents losing from the disequalizing change in the distribution of shares have to be more patient than before to produce the efficient level of effort when the punishment is renegotiation-proof and coalition-proof. I

δN ≤ δXP

Redistribution and Cooperation

Coexistence of 2 coalitions If all know that some are so poor that πkN > πkC and therefore cannot afford to cooperate, the rich players are expected not to punish them.

Observation If a subset of agents do not cooperate because of a low λk (such that πkC < πkN ), a low-producing (putting in the Nash level of effort) and a high-producing (providing the efficient level of effort) coalition can coexist. 2 players with a high enough positive share are needed for the cooperative effort to be produced.

In the presence of 2 coalitions, the total level of effort put in the 1 2 P P P project is i ei = j∈nC λjγ−1 + k∈nD λkγ−1 .

Increasing inequality, I

D → D ; C, 4+ total level of effort

I

D → C, depends on γ (≥ 3 : 4− ,∃˜ γ ∈ [2, 3[: 4 = 0, < γ˜ : 4+ )

I

D → D, depends on γ (< 3 : 4+ , = 3 : 4 = 0,> 3 : 4− )

In the presence of 2 coalitions, the total level of effort put in the 1 2 P P P project is i ei = j∈nC λjγ−1 + k∈nD λkγ−1 .

Increasing inequality, I

D → D ; C, 4+ total level of effort

I

D → C, depends on γ (≥ 3 : 4− ,∃˜ γ ∈ [2, 3[: 4 = 0, < γ˜ : 4+ )

I

D → D, depends on γ (< 3 : 4+ , = 3 : 4 = 0,> 3 : 4− )

A disequalizing redistribution can therefore increase or decrease the total level of efforts put in for the project, depending on the value of γ and the status of the concerned players. ; U shape

In the presence of 2 coalitions, the total level of effort put in the 1 2 P P P project is i ei = j∈nC λjγ−1 + k∈nD λkγ−1 .

Increasing inequality, I

D → D ; C, 4+ total level of effort

I

D → C, depends on γ (≥ 3 : 4− ,∃˜ γ ∈ [2, 3[: 4 = 0, < γ˜ : 4+ )

I

D → D, depends on γ (< 3 : 4+ , = 3 : 4 = 0,> 3 : 4− )

A disequalizing redistribution can therefore increase or decrease the total level of efforts put in for the project, depending on the value of γ and the status of the concerned players. ; U shape

Diminishing inequality There are cases where, following their best interest, the rich players would benefit from redistributing part of their share to the poor so that the latter can afford to cooperate.

Outside Option Nash Reversion ∗

(1 − δ)πiC + δπiN < πiC ⇒ δ > ∗

(1 − δ)πiC + δπiS < πiC ⇒ δ >



πiC −πiC ∗ πiC −πiN ∗ πiC −πiC ∗ πiC −πiS

⇒ πiC > max(πiN , πiS )

RPCP Besides conditions on δXA and δXP , (1 − δ)πiP + δπiC > πiS ⇒ δ > ⇒ πiC > max(πiN , πiS )

πiS −πiP πiC −πiP

Summary Table

πiC



↑ πiS

>

πiC

>

↑ ∗ (1 − δ)πiC + δπiS

πiN

↑ πiC

↑ πiC if δN < δ

if δN→S < δ Restricted access to the project πiC ↑ πiS



> ↑ ∗ (1 − δ)πiC + δπiS

πiN

> ↑ ∗ (1 − δ)πiC + δπiN

πiC ↑ ∗ (1 − δ)πiC + δπiN

Conclusion

I

Inequality reduces the scope for cooperation, efficiency (through 4+ δN or δXP ).

I

Possibility of coexistence of a cooperating and deviating coalition.

I

Share inequality can have a U-shaped relationship with the aggregate level of effort.

I

Repetition of the game and outside options increase the scope for redistribution.

Condition Ex ante, the punishment must be such that deviations are deterred. For a return to cooperation after the punishment phase (and for preventing the deviators from alternating between deviating and being punished): ∗



(1 − δ)πiC + δ(1 − δ)πiP + δ 2 πiC < πiC ⇒ δXA >

πiC − πiC πiC − πiP

Condition Ex post, the punishment must be such that deviations from the punishment are deterred. ∗

(1 − δ)πiP

+ δπiC

>

∗ (1 − δ)πiP

0 + δ(1 − δ)πiP

+ δ 2 πiC

∂δXP > 0 ⇒ arg max δXP = nD ∂nD∗ nD ∗ ∈(1,nD )

⇒ δXP

π P − πiP > iC 0 πi − πiP

Condition The payoff of the punishers must be greater when conforming than when deviating from punishing and then conforming, i.e. ∗ π 1/P > π 1/P . This condition prevents punishers to skip the punishment phase. If λi = n−1 , we get: γ

γ nC ∗ (R − R ∗ ) > (R γ − R ∗ ) n

I

it must be always true if nC ∗ = 1.

I

if it is not true, when nC ∗ > 1, this deviating subcoalition cannot be credible.

Condition For the equilibrium to be coalition-proof, no deviation should be 1/P ∗ 1/P ∗∗ credible, i.e. πi < πi . If λi = n−1 and nC ∗∗ = 1, −γ

γ (1 − n γ−1 ) < −1 n (1 − n γ−1 ) 2

We know from those two conditions that, if R ≡ eiN ≡ λiγ−1 , no credible coalition of punishers can deviate from giving a punishment. R ≡ eiN ⇒ δXP >

πiN − πiP πiC − πiP

As no deviation of punishers is credible when the punished conform to their punishment, a fortiori, it is also the case when some punished refuse to undergo the penalty.

Condition The payoff from punishing a deviating coalition must be greater or 1/P equal than the payoff from generalized cooperation, i.e. πi ≥ πiC .

−2

γ

λi = n−1 ⇒ P = n γ−1 [n γ−1 (1 − γ −1 ) − (nC − γ −1 )] n1D λi 6= n−1 ⇒   2−γ γ P γ−1 γ−1 1 2 P P λ (1−λ ) j∈nC j j   λ γ−1 − λ γ−1 − γ −1 P j = P λk k∈nD

λk

i∈n

i

j∈nC

j

nC

Inequality and a Repeated Joint Project

define R and P: efforts when punishing and being punished. Punishment scheme: As soon as a coalition deviates, the cooperative agents play a retaliation level ...

395KB Sizes 1 Downloads 148 Views

Recommend Documents

INEQUALITY AND INEFFICIENCY IN JOINT PROJECTS*
Dec 8, 2004 - complemented by similar efforts elsewhere in the network for the ... perfect equality of shares maximises social surplus over all share vectors.

Repeated Signaling and Firm Dynamics
We thank the seminar participants at Columbia University, Dartmouth College, New York University, London. Business School .... In our model, firms with positive information choose higher capital stocks and credibly ...... in simulated data, the corre

Repeated Signaling and Firm Dynamics
Mar 17, 2010 - University of California, Berkeley ... firms with negative private information have negative leverage, issue equity, and overin- vest. ... We thank the seminar participants at Columbia University, Dartmouth College, New York University

Repeated Interaction and Rating Inflation
ently, rating agencies ignored available data on risks when rating mortgage ..... the rating published, and the CRA publishes a rating every time it is hired (no ...... discussed the connection between ancillary services fees and rating inflation.

Inequality and ability
explain very little of the increase in inequality, technology is suspected to be responsible .... indicate that the OLS returns to mental skills and education are biased downward in the ... E.D. Gould / Labour Economics 12 (2005) 169–189. 171 ...

Complexity and repeated implementation
May 6, 2015 - 7 Note also that complexity cost enters the agents' preferences lexicographically. All our results below hold when the decision maker admits a ...

Inequality and ability
3247; fax: +972-2-581-6071. E-mail address: [email protected] (E.D. Gould). www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase .... sional, service, and blue-collar occupations, the increasing importance of unobserved general ability within all three ...

LDC- Repeated Questions and Answers.pdf
c1163J. s(m (c36rD'ejscT)o I)1))1)3. rn42-3 @1)m'eism3 wgoyml. ca6)J0 1)rnJSc6)S S. i10 cmTho. (locO,3SC)l c1OC)J1 aec1D3. m1960-i 26nJ1)6nJ31)1 cn3.

Taxation of Human Capital and Wage Inequality: A ...
the impact of labour market (tax) policies on the determination of wage inequality, focusing on male workers and .... Europe. Finally, a number of recent papers share some common modeling elements with ours but ..... Figure 2 plots the progressivity

Taxation of Human Capital and Wage Inequality: A ... - Fatih Guvenen
JEL Codes: E24, E62 ...... (Amsterdam: North-Holland) 18. ... KRUEGER, D. (2006), “On the Optimal Progressivity of the Income Tax Code”, Journal of Monetary.

Heterogeneous trade costs and wage inequality: A ...
We use data on trade flows from the Feenstra database, note that data pre- and post-1984 ...... All regressions include an intercept. The change in 50/10 wage ...

Efficient Repeated Implementation: Supplementary Material
strategy bi except that at (ht,θt) it reports z + 1. Note from the definition of mechanism g∗ and the transition rules of R∗ that such a deviation at (ht,θt) does not ...

Efficient Repeated Implementation
‡Faculty of Economics, Cambridge, CB3 9DD, United Kingdom; Hamid. ... A number of applications naturally fit this description. In repeated voting or .... behind the virtual implementation literature to demonstrate that, in a continuous time,.

Efficient Repeated Implementation
[email protected] ..... at,θ ∈ A is the outcome implemented in period t and state θ. Let A∞ denote the set ... t=1Ht. A typical history of mechanisms and.