Is Cognitive Science Usefully Cast as Complexity Science? Guy Van Orden and Damian G. Stephen CAP Center for Cognition, Action & Perception. University of Cincinnati

Wyss Institute for Biologically Inspired Engineering. Harvard University

Correspondence: Guy Van Orden, CAP Center, ML 0376, University of Cincinnati, OH 45221-0376, USA. Phone: (513) 321-0425 Email: [email protected] or Damian G. Stephen, Wyss Institute for Biologically Inspired Engineering, Harvard University, 3 Blackfan Circle, Floor 5, Boston, MA 02115, USA. Phone: (703) 300-3375 Email: [email protected] Acknowledgments: Preparation of this introduction was supported by NSF grants to Guy Van Orden (BCS #0843133; DHB #0728743). Running Head: Complexity Theory Keywords: complexity, cognition, bifurcation, nonstationary equilibria, qualitative change.

Abstract Readers of TopiCS are invited to join a debate about the utility of ideas and methods of complexity science. The topics of debate include empirical instances of qualitative change in cognitive activity and whether this empirical work demonstrates sufficiently the empirical flags of complexity. In addition, new phenomena discovered by complexity scientists, and motivated by complexity theory, call into question some basic assumptions of conventional cognitive science such as stable equilibria and homogeneous variance. The articles and commentaries that appear in this issue also illustrate a new debate style format to TopiCS.

Complexity theory is a special branch of chaos theory or nonlinear dynamical systems theory distinguished by its emphasis on qualitative change. Chaos theory is a mathematical theory and has been applied successfully across a broad swath of natural phenomena –– including climate change, dripping faucets, and the kinematics of living beings –– basically anything that changes over time such that its next state is determined by its previous state and the rules that govern how states change over time. Complexity theory emphasizes the straw that breaks the camel’s back –– the incremental changes in behavior, manner, and emotion that might lead from “Are you busy tonight?” to “Let’s get married!” Complexity theory concerns how small local changes precipitate qualitative change in the behavior of a system. Much inspiration for thinking about qualitative change in this way came from “far-from-equilibrium” thermodynamics. Living systems generally express dynamics that are far-from-equilibrium. For example, when the average performances of children at different ages are compared, and these are compared across a lifespan of development (with the average performances of adults and the elderly), the estimated mean values change appreciably throughout the lifespan (as does the pattern of dispersion of measured values around the mean). Instead of measured values gravitating toward the stable average value of a stable equilibrium, development expresses nonstationary and unstable equilibria. As a consequence, the observed average values simply do not carry the same weight, by themselves, as they would to characterize stationary and stable equilibria. Stock market indices are nonstationary in the same way, expressing the ups and downs in economic developments of market systems (Taleb, 2007).

Most work in cognitive science has treated empirical data as though they do yield stable average values, with theoretical origins in stable equilibria. Please notice that the basis of the distinction between truly complex systems versus complicated behavior does not rest on whether an average can be computed –– naturally, any collected set of measurements will have a mean value –– only not all measured data gravitate toward stable mean values. Yet far and away the majority of laboratory studies in which cognitive and behavioral activities were measured have presupposed that the measured values do gravitate toward stable averages, and that task and cognitive effects are first and foremost discovered in the direction and magnitude of change between average values (however, cf. Ashby, Tien, & Balikrishnan, 1993; Balakrishnan & Ashby, 1991; Luce, 1986; Maddox et al., 1998; Michell, 1999; Molenaar, 2008). The empirical distinction at issue, then, is between the dynamics of stable equilibria and far-from-equilibrium dynamics –– that is, whether a mean value’s variance stays put or changes when more data are collected, and whether mean values provide sufficient and reliable information about the system under study. If mean values are not stable equilibria then the empirical focus may shift to more reliable and informative aspects of a system’s behavior, and theory development may explain these alternative aspects. Understandably, a shift of this consequence could require a scientist to make qualitative changes in the empirical methods employed and in the theoretical and conceptual tools brought to bear. Consequently, a shift to the theory and methods of complexity science would naturally require persuasive and motivating justification. This special issue of TopiCS provides the forum for a contemporary debate about whether such justification yet exists.

From the perspectives taken in the target articles, this debate hangs on the observations already made about the character of qualitative change in human behavior and conscious experience –– the coming into existence of a new insight in problem solving, the reorganization of mind and body after brain damage (Dixon, Holden, Mirman, & Stephen, this volume), the pragmatic choices for sensible speech (Gibbs & Van Orden, this volume), spontaneous qualitative change generally (Riley, Shockley, & Van Orden, this volume), and the qualities of phenomenology that suggest coupling among brain, body, and environment (Silberstein & Chemero, this volume). If these observations prove to be sufficiently general and reliable they will motivate the alternative perspective, emphasizing the coordination of mind and body (synergies) in human activities instead of centralized cognitive control of behavior (Turvey, 2007). This emphasis on coordination stems from seeing the origins of qualitative change as a reordering or reorganization of how the mind and body interact –– not a switch from one mental process to another, different, control process (Hollis, Kloos, & Van Orden, 2009). The mathematical term for a qualitative change is bifurcation, which refers to the tipping point between different potential spontaneous reorganizations of a system’s behavior. The corresponding term in physics is phase transition. Bifurcations can be local or global. On the one hand, when a person corrects their course of action on the way to an error, ending in the correct course of action after all (e.g., Spivey, 2007), we might call this a local bifurcation. On the other hand, when a person changes the overall strategy with which they approach the same task, we might call this a global bifurcation (Stephen, Boncoddo, Dixon, & Magnuson, 2009; Stephen, Dixon, & Isenhower, 2009). Almost all of the empirical work in cognitive science conducted under the umbrella of complexity

theory tests for the presence of the marker phenomena of bifurcations, the empirical flags of behavior that are predicted to occur near the tipping points of qualitative change (e.g., Van Orden, Kloos, & Wallot, 2011, is a review). For example Wagenmakers, van der Maas, and Farrell (this volume) discuss the use of catastrophe theory, which is one source of the empirical flags used by complexity scientists. Complexity theory has knit these empirical flags together with the empirical flags articulated in thermodynamics to characterize criticality, symmetry, and metastability. Criticality concerns the general implications of tipping points; symmetry generalizes what it means that a system can entertain more than one option, simultaneously, for reorganization; and metastability concerns the consequences for dynamics of simultaneous multiple options for reorganization. This melding of mathematics and physics into a more coherent understanding of qualitative change was one mark of progress during the last half of the 20th century, giving a more comprehensive and exacting expression of qualitative change. The target articles all draw on predictions derived from mathematical expressions of qualitative change, the theoretical basis for the work described. What remains at issue, however, as the commentators clarify, is whether the corroboration already discovered by complexity scientists is sufficient to engender a sea change in how we go about cognitive science. We invite you to consider the kinds of evidence that the target articles illustrate and, if you haven’t done so already, please join this discussion down the line.

References Ashby, F. G., Tien, J.-Y., & Balikrishnan. J. D. (1993). Response time distributions in memory scanning. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 37, 526–555. Balakrishnan, J. D. & Ashby, F. G. (1991). Is subitizing a unique numerical ability? Perception & Psychophysics, 50, 555-564. Estes, W. K. & Maddox, W. T. (2005). Risks of drawing inferences about cognitive processes from model fits to individual versus average performance. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 12, 403-408 W. T. Maddox, F. G. Ashby, L. R. Gottlob. (1998). Response time distributions in multidimensional perceptual categorization. Perception & Psychophysics, 60, 620-637. J. Michell, J. (1999). Measurement in psychology. A critical history of a methodological concept. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Dixon, J. A., Holden, J. G., Mirman, D., & Stephen, D. G. (this volume). Multifractal dynamics in the emergence of cognitive structure. Topics in Cognitive Science. Gibbs, R. W., & Van Orden, G. (this volume). Pragmatic choice in conversation. Topics in Cognitive Science. Hollis, G., Kloos, H., & Van Orden, G. (2009). Origins of order in cognitive activity. In S. J. Guastello, M. Koopmans, & D. Pincus (Eds.) Chaos and Complexity in Psychology: The Theory of Nonlinear Dynamical Systems, 206-241. NYC: Cambridge University Press.

Luce, R. D. (1986). Response times: Their role in inferring elementary mental organization. New York: Oxford University Press. Molenaar, P. C. M. (2008). On the implications of the classical ergodic theorems: Analysis of developmental processes has to focus on intraindividual variation. Developmental Psychobiology, 50, 60–69. Riley, M. A., Shockley, K., & Van Orden, G. (this volume). Learning from the body about the mind. Topics in Cognitive Science. Spivey, M. J. (2007). The continuity of mind. New York: Oxford University Press. Stephen, D. G., Boncoddo, R. A., Dixon, J. A., & Magnuson, J. S. (2009). The dynamics of insight: Mathematical discovery as a phase transition. Memory & Cognition, 37, 1132-1149. Stephen, D. G., Dixon J. A., & Isenhower, R. W. (2009). Dynamics of representational change: Entropy, action, and cognition. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 35, 1811-1822. Taleb, N. N. (2007). The black swan. NY: Random House. Turvey, M.T. (2007). Action and perception at the level of synergies. Human Movement Science, 26, 657-697. Van Orden, G., Kloos, H., & Wallot, S. (2011). Living in the pink: Intentionality, wellness, and complexity. In C. A. Hooker (Ed.) Philosophy of Complex Systems, Volume 10: Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. Amsterdam: Elsevier. Wagenmakers, E.-J., van der Maas, H. L. J., & Farrell, S. (this volume). Abstract concepts require concrete models: Why cognitive scientists have not yet embraced

nonlinearly-coupled, dynamical, self-organized critical, synergistic, scale-free, exquisitely context-sensitive, interaction-dominant, fractal, interdependent brainbody-niche systems. Topics in Cognitive Science.

Is Cognitive Science Usefully Cast as Complexity ...

Most work in cognitive science has treated empirical data as though they do yield ... error, ending in the correct course of action after all (e.g., Spivey, 2007), we ...

101KB Sizes 5 Downloads 157 Views

Recommend Documents

Physical Complexity and Cognitive Evolution
Regular object (process): regular pattern short decription (compression) possible. 0101010101010101010101010101… million repetitions of 01. Random ...

PHYSICAL COMPLEXITY AND COGNITIVE ...
tion is not stored within a (genetic) sequence but rather in the correlations between the sequence ... Evolution is a slow process and therefore obtaining exact data is dif- ficult. .... Self-referential cognition - a 'Big Bang' of complexity in cogn

Physical Complexity and Cognitive Evolution
Digital organisms (digitalia) are self-replicating computer programs (sequences of instructions) that mutate and compete. (for space and computer time). • 3 conditions of evolution: replication, variation (mutation), ... It might be fruitful to gen

THE PHENOMENAL STANCE Cognitive science is ... - Springer Link
think of them as mere mechanisms seems at best counterintu- itive and unhelpful. More often it may strike us as ludicrous, or even abhorrent. We are 'intuitive dualists' (Bloom, 2004). We view people and objects as fundamentally different sorts of th

THE PHENOMENAL STANCE Cognitive science is ...
same kind, and comes from the same source, as that sur- rounding any ... tional stance and the physical stance by mapping it onto the distinction between ...

Processing Scalar Implicatures - Cognitive Science
ims. Neo-Gricean approaches (e.g. Levinson (2000), Matsumoto (1995)) stay close to Grice's account, while Relevance Theory (Wilson and Sperber (1995), Carston (1998)) departs ... ims, on the basis of which conversational implicatures are worked out.

Physical complexity and cognitive evolution Peter ...
principles as suggested by several authors (Penrose 1994, Satinover 2001). Since indeterminism observed in quantum measurements is sometimes interpreted as fundamental time asymmetry, there is an intriguing possibility that a deeper link might connec

BC Sub Cast Codes as per Childinfo.pdf
and included in ST list vide. G.O.Ms.No.149, SW, Dt.03.05.1978). 14) Medari or Mahendra. 15) Mondivaru, Mondibanda, Banda . 16) Nayi-Brahmin/Nayee-Brahmin (Mangali), Mangala and. Bhajantri. 17) Nakkala (deleted vide. G.O.Ms.No.21, BCW (C2) Dept., Dt.

Worlds and Cognitive Science
Department of Cognitive Science, Case Western Reserve University. 605 Crawford ... worlds in computer science and the web (Steen et al. 2006). He is also the ... as we read. Detailed meaning construction at the level of ... in The Sims Online.

Position Announcement Cognitive Science and ... -
Greater Phoenix metropolitan area. CTI embodies the polytechnic values of engaged learning, applied research, engagement with industry, and innovation and entrepreneurship. CTI is enjoying a period of substantial growth and now enrolls more than 3,40

science cognitive - narrative education english.pdf
Page 1 of 3. COGNITIVE SCIENCE - Narrative education. Let's start this discussion with a concrete example, a setting, created by. Montessoris. Applied in South America in classes where students choose their topic,. it produces the same effort without

Logical Omniscience as a Computational Complexity ...
stant specification for JL ∈ {J, JD, JT, J4, JD4, LP}, then JLCS as an epistemic system with simple reflected fragment rJLCS passes LOT (with respect to a certain proof system). In the last two statements, we assume that CS(·) is com- putable in p

Components of Self-Complexity as Buffers for ...
Sep 29, 2007 - superior predictive power over the use of the SC-D measure. ... 1979) is a standard self-report scale of depression used widely in a variety of ...

Components of Self-Complexity as Buffers for ...
Sep 29, 2007 - by eight advanced clinical psychology students on a 0–3 scale for their ..... and the subjective nature of this measure are far from ideal and call ... The measure of depressive symptoms was the Center for Epidemiological.

Satellite based land use and landscape complexity indices as ...
model. We used a simple linear least square model for all species groups with the exception of the threatened species where we used a poisson model because ..... Randomization, bootstrap and Monte-Carlo. Methods in biology. Chapman & Hall, New York.

Inference complexity as a model-selection criterion for ...
I n Pacific Rim International. Conference on ArtificialIntelligence, pages 399 -4 1 0, 1 998 . [1 4] I rina R ish, M ark Brodie, Haiqin Wang, and ( heng M a. I ntelligent prob- ing: a cost-efficient approach to fault diagnosis in computer networks. S

Is Computer Science Science?
Apr 28, 2005 - ... granting CS degrees for 40 years. ... Computer science meets every criterion for being a science, but it has a ... The lexicographers offer two.

When Physics is Not “Just Physics”: Complexity ...
cognitive phenomena with a suspicion that biological and cognitive systems, capable of ..... ena. Although Euclid's fifth axiom itself has little to do the neurobiological sciences, the revolution ..... Westerhoff HV, Winder C, Messiha H, Simeonidis.

Bilingualism as a protective factor against cognitive ageing (PDF ...
Full-text (PDF) | Resumen El control atencional permite a los bilingües utilizar ambos lenguajes de forma alternante minimizando las intrusiones de una lengua ...

Using Fuzzy Cognitive Maps as a Decision Support ... - Springer Link
no cut-and-dried solutions” [2]. In International Relations theory, ..... Fuzzy Cognitive Maps,” Information Sciences, vol. 101, pp. 109-130, 1997. [9] E. H. Shortliffe ...

Early Visual Cortex as a Multiscale Cognitive ... - Floris de Lange
18 Jul 2016 - Abstract. Neurons in early visual cortical areas not only represent incoming visual in- formation but are also engaged by higher level cognitive processes, including attention, working memory, imagery, and decision-making. Are these cog

Cast P. C., Cast Kristin - Dom Nocy 04 - Nieposkromiona.pdf ...
340. Page 3 of 353. Cast P. C., Cast Kristin - Dom Nocy 04 - Nieposkromiona.pdf. Cast P. C., Cast Kristin - Dom Nocy 04 - Nieposkromiona.pdf. Open. Extract.

Language as shaped by the brain - Cognitive Neuroscience Lab
Division of Psychology and Language Sciences, University College London,. London, WC1E ...... are inner selves with consciousness and free will (Blackmore. 1999 ...... NOTE. 1. An unabridged draft of this commentary is available online at:.