Cognition 90 (2003) 201–204 www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT

Discussion

Monotonicity and syllogistic inference: a reply to Newstead Bart Geurts Department of Philosophy, University of Nijmegen, P.O. Box 9103, 6500 HD Nijmegen, The Netherlands Received 11 June 2003; accepted 11 June 2003

Newstead’s critique is an exercise in carpet-bombing: he doesn’t raise one big objection but a host of smaller ones. I hope I will be excused if I address only a handful. Let me start with a brief synopsis. Experimental investigations of human reasoning invariably use linguistic tasks. Subjects are to say whether this or that sentence follows from a given set of sentences, or to draw their own conclusions, etc. Hence, human reasoning, as studied by Newstead and his fellow psychologists, is at least partly a matter of linguistic processing. In particular, since inferences are drawn on the basis of what the premisses mean, human reasoning, as studied by psychologists, is at least partly a matter of semantic interpretation. We don’t know how big that part is, nor whether it can be neatly separated from “genuine” processes of inference (as is often assumed), but it is there. As interpretation precedes inference, it is only to be expected that reasoning is affected more by salient semantic properties than by others. By “salient” I mean such properties that play a prominent part in the interpretation of language. My paper explored the possibility that reasoning with quantifiers is influenced by what are known to be the salient properties of quantifying expressions, and especially by their monotonicity properties. In order to flesh out this suggestion, I presented a simple inference system, which was embedded in an equally simple processing model, with a view to showing “that even a crude processing model can produce reasonable predictions” (Geurts, 2003, p. 243). My idea was that if a toy model does reasonably well, a more sophisticated model is likely to do better.

E-mail address: [email protected] (B. Geurts). 0022-2860/$ - see front matter q 2003 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(03)00118-5

202

B. Geurts / Cognition 90 (2003) 201–204

A large part of Newstead’s critique is devoted to arguing that my model is simplistic and that its predictions aren’t perfect. However, there really was no need to argue for this, because I had already conceded as much. More interesting is the question whether the model’s imperfections matter, and here Newstead and I appear to disagree, although the disagreement is more superficial than Newstead suggests. A case in point is the axiom (Newstead calls it a “rule”) that “all” entails “some”, to which Newstead objects on two grounds. First, “this principle seems implausible since it breaches Gricean conversational implicatures: ‘some’ would not normally be used if ‘all’ were the case.” Secondly, Newstead rejects my assumption that this “rule [read: ‘axiom’] can be applied with no cognitive effort.” The first objection cuts no ice, because if a conclusion is evidently weaker than its premisses, people are generally reluctant to say that it follows, even if they treat the inference as valid (cf. my remarks on “or”; Geurts, 2003, p. 248, n. 21). For example, most people will accept that the first of the following arguments is valid, which implies that they accept the validity of the second argument, as well, even if they are reluctant to explicitly endorse it: If anybody is sick, the meeting is cancelled. Everybody is sick. [ The meeting is cancelled. Everybody is sick. [ Someone is sick. As noted in my paper (Geurts, 2003, p. 226, n. 2), the inference from “all” to “some” is not an ordinary inference. It is a presupposition, hence part of the lexical content of “all”, and a salient part at that. Which is to say that processing the word “all” will suffice to trigger it. This justifies the assumption that the “inference” becomes available at negligible cost. I admit that modelling this presupposition as an axiom was a makeshift, though in the context of my paper it was an innocuous simplification. See Geurts (1999) for a treatment that is rather less naive. Although Newstead lavishes attention on secondary features of my theory, he also objects to its main tenet, which is that monotonicity plays a role in human reasoning. To begin with, Newstead suggests that on my account monotonicity inferences are complex. This suggestion is misleading. First, my theory is, if anything, simpler than its competitors. This becomes especially clear when my monotonicity rule is compared with its counterpart in Ford’s (1995) theory (which Newstead seems to approve of), which is less general and much more complex. Secondly, Newstead’s objection blithely ignores a crucial argument in my paper, namely, that there is weighty independent evidence for the claim that people routinely and effortlessly use monotonicity properties (of any type of expression). In my paper I mustered various sorts of linguistic evidence for this claim, but there is experimental evidence as well. For example, Crain and his colleagues have demonstrated that children as young as

B. Geurts / Cognition 90 (2003) 201–204

203

3;11 know that the first of the following arguments is valid whereas the second one is not (e.g. Boster & Crain, 1993): Every troll who ordered French-fries or onion rings got some mustard. [ Every troll who ordered French-fries got some mustard. Every ghostbuster will choose a cat or a pig. [ Every ghostbuster will choose pig. Apparently, even very young children are sensitive to the monotonicity properties of the universal quantifier, which entail that “or” licenses a conjunctive inference if it occurs in the first argument of “every” but not if it occurs in the second argument. As always, when taken on its own this fact doesn’t prove much, but in conjunction with other findings amassed by linguists, philosophers, and psychologists, it is compelling evidence for the claim that monotonicity is a fundamental concept in interpretation as well as inference. It is important to note that, amidst a barrage of objections, Newstead actually concedes that there is evidence that people use monotonicity inferences like the ones I propose. This means that he and I agree on what I take to be the main point. For even if he argues that my theory is flawed in all sorts of ways, we agree that one of the strategies for syllogistic reasoning involves replacing set-denoting expressions. But then Newstead can hardly fail to support the main objective of my paper, which is to show that this strategy follows naturally from general principles emerging from semantics, language acquisition, and so on. Based on protocol studies by Ford (1995) and Bacon, Handley, and Newstead (2003), Newstead claims that there is a “basic distinction between verbal and spatial reasoners”, from which he concludes that my theory can at best explain the behaviour of every second reasoner. Although I fully agree that there are likely to be different modes of reasoning, and I would be happy to have accounted for any one of them, I don’t think this is correct. What Ford and Bacon et al. have shown is that if subjects are given pencil and paper for solving syllogistic problems, some of them will draw pictures in the process. But this doesn’t even begin to show that underlying this behaviour there is a special mode of reasoning. Indeed, granted the existence of a substitution strategy for solving syllogistic problems, there is no principled difference between manipulating set-denoting terms and set-denoting diagrams, like Euler circles, for example. Hence, Ford and Bacon et al.’s results fail to establish that there is a distinctive spatial style of syllogistic reasoning. Newstead directs several objections against my discussion of “at most”. To begin with, he doubts my finding that arguments with “at most” are sometimes more complex than corresponding arguments with “at least” or “some”. Newstead considers this a dubious result because he didn’t obtain anything like it in a study of his own, which isn’t surprising because already in my own experiment the effect showed up only in two-premiss arguments, not in single-premiss arguments. Apparently, “at most” can make a comparatively difficult task more difficult, but has no measurable effect on easy tasks. Furthermore, the data I reported have in the meantime been confirmed by a new experiment (not yet published). So I cannot agree with Newstead on this point. On the other hand, I concur with his criticism of the tentative explanation I suggested; but I think I have a better story now. If a sentence contains several quantifiers, their monotonicity

204

B. Geurts / Cognition 90 (2003) 201–204

properties may or may not mesh. For example, “some” has the same monotonicity properties as “more than three”, while “less than three” is different, so the combination “some/more than three” is more harmonic than the combination “some/less than three”. The experiment referred to above provided evidence that harmony, in the sense just explained, is a measure of complexity. For example, the first of the following arguments (both of which are valid) proves to be much easier than the second (96% vs. 51% correct): At least 3 reporters played against more than 2 foresters. All foresters were communists. [ At least 3 reporters played against more than 2 communists. At least 3 reporters played against less than 2 foresters. All communists were foresters. [ At least 3 reporters played against less than 2 communists. What I would like to suggest is that quantifiers like “at most three” and “less than three” are themselves not perfectly harmonic: they are downward entailing but contain an expression that is upward entailing, namely “three”. It is for this reason that they are inherently more difficult than the other quantifiers. If correct, this analysis shows, in yet another way, how the concept of monotonicity helps to explain why some arguments are more difficult than others.

References Bacon, A. M., Handley, S. J., & Newstead, S. E. (2003). Individual differences in strategies for syllogistic reasoning. Thinking and Reasoning, 9, 97–131. Boster, C., & Crain, S. (1993). On children’s understanding of every and or. Proceedings of early cognition and transition to language. Austin, TX: University of Texas at Austin. Ford, M. (1995). Two modes of mental representation and problem solution in syllogistic reasoning. Cognition, 54, 1– 71. Geurts, B. (1999). Presuppositions and pronouns. Oxford: Elsevier. Geurts, B. (2003). Reasoning with quantifiers. Cognition, 86, 223–251.

Monotonicity and syllogistic inference: a reply to ...

For example, Crain and his colleagues have demonstrated that children as ... other hand, I concur with his criticism of the tentative explanation I suggested; but I ...

55KB Sizes 1 Downloads 275 Views

Recommend Documents

Monotonicity and Processing Load - CiteSeerX
The council houses are big enough for families with three kids. c. You may attend ..... data, a repeated measures analysis of variance was conducted with three.

True, False, Paranormal and Designated: A Reply to Beall C.S. ...
C.S. JENKINS .... Of course, that only means its true-in-real-life that .5 ... Finally, of course, if one takes the second option, one places a familiar, and implausible, ...

hell, vagueness, and justice: a reply to sider
All rights reserved. HELL, VAGUENESS, AND JUSTICE: A REPLY TO SIDER. Trent Dougherty and Ted Poston. Ted Sider's paper “Hell and Vagueness” challenges a ... sponses because our argument retains all the original premises of Sider's ..... Eye, whom

hell, vagueness, and justice: a reply to sider
Reflection sug- gests little reason to endorse (E). Consider the following parable (perhaps best read with a British accent, in the style of Monty Python).

Reply to Clanton and Forcehimes
there are many ways of addressing moral conflicts that are consistent with the full employment of reason. Epistemic version of pluralism, by contrast, need.

Reply to Shiner
My response will take the form of a series of questions followed by my own proposed .... assurances in his reply that ' it looks like Kristeller may not have been ...

Reply to Jackendoff
Unfair to facts. Philosophical Papers. J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock (eds.),. 154–174. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chomsky, Noam (2000). New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Fodor, Jerry (19

Preference Monotonicity and Information Aggregation ...
{01} which assigns to every tuple (μ x s) a degenerate probability of voting for P. Formally, we define our equilibrium in the following way. DEFINITION 1—Equilibrium: The strategy profile where every independent voter i uses σ∗ i (μ x s) is a

Moral parochialism misunderstood: a reply to Piazza ... - Colin Holbrook
Jan 22, 2016 - 4Department of Anthropology, University of California, Santa Barbara, Santa Barbara, CA ... judgements exist in all of the societies examined.

Moral parochialism misunderstood: a reply to Piazza ... - Colin Holbrook
Jan 22, 2016 - and Social Change, Arizona State University, ... 1Department of Anthropology and Center for Behavior, Evolution, and Culture, University of California, ... ness of an action (from wrong to not wrong or good) when it was.

Damasio, A Reply to McGilchrist's Review of Descartes' Error.pdf ...
neuroscience, the history of artificial intelligence, and even the history of. psychology, as far as reason and emotion are concerned, he would not puzzle. over the ...

Richard Rorty - On Ethnocentrism - A Reply to Clifford Geertz.pdf ...
Page 1 of 1. Page 1. Richard Rorty - On Ethnocentrism - A Reply to Clifford Geertz.pdf. Richard Rorty - On Ethnocentrism - A Reply to Clifford Geertz.pdf. Open.

Liberal Pluralism: A Reply to Talisse
Jan 22, 2004 - Liberal pluralism is a comprehensive account and justification of ..... adopt an aggressively defensive stance designed to yield as little ground as ... are prima facie bads of a pretty high order and stand in need of justification.

A Theoretical Burden or Just Load? A Reply to Tsal and ...
tasks and distractor measures provides strong support for load .... compass four to five items (e.g., Fisher, 1982; Kahneman, Treis- man, & Gibbs, 1992; Yantis ...

Reply to Lee and Baxter: Perceptual deficits cannot explain ... - PNAS
Feb 9, 2010 - 39120 Magdeburg, Germany; and dGerman Centre for Neuro- degenerative Disorders–Magdeburg, O.v.G University, 39120 Mag- deburg, Germany. 1. Lee ACH, Baxter MG (2010) The hippocampus and configural-relational information: A relationship

Reply to Comment by Agrawal and Verma on ...
doi:10.1016/j.gca.2007.04.021. E-mail address: [email protected] www.elsevier.com/locate/gca. Geochimica et Cosmochimica Acta 71 (2007) 3391– ...

Receive, View and Reply to New Email
Receive, View and Reply to New Email. Log into your Gmail account to view your inbox. To open an email, simply click it in your email list. This will open the ...

Finnigan Reply to Garfield and Hansen
University of Auckland. I begin by warmly thanking Professors ... Buddhist thought for not having the resources to fit this account. In replying to my argument, they ...

Inferentialism and the categoricity problem: reply to ...
Nov 10, 2008 - In a recent paper, Panu Raatikainen argues that this view—call it logical ... ‡Arché, AHRC Center for Logic, Language, Metaphysics and Epistemology, University .... In this framework, Carnap's original problem doesn't arise.

Reply to Carlo Severi
A good theory should anticipate on data. Carlo ... Indeed, mvët singers constantly remind their audience that the real enunciators of the poem are ... of the Sky. Note that the addressee may also be several entities at the same time: a ... sion in t

Reply to Questionnaire-7th CPC.pdf
Copy to Media CentreA{FIR. Ph.:011-23343305,65027299,R1y.22283,22626,Fax:011-23744013,R\y.22 Z,febgr:am:RAILMAZDOR. E-mail : gs @ nfirindia.com; ...

ICC-Reply-To-SLC.pdf
www.icc-cricket.com. From: David Richardson. Sent: Thursday, February 06, 2014 3:39 PM. To: Iain Higgins. Subject: FW: F & CA COMMERCIAL RIGHTS - WORKING GROUP - POSITION PAPER/REVISED. PROPOSED 'RESOLUTIONS'. Page 3 of 3. ICC-Reply-To-SLC.pdf. ICC-R