On Noncooperative Oligopoly in Large Economies∗ Francesca Busetto†, Giulio Codognato‡, and Sayantan Ghosal§ March 2003

Abstract In this paper, we compare a mixed version of a model of noncooperative exchange, originally proposed by Lloyd S. Shapley, with the respecification `a la Cournot-Walras of this model, originally introduced by Busetto and Codognato (2002). We propose an example showing that the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model does not coincide with the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations of its respecification. From this nonequivalence result, the mixed version of the Shapley’s model emerges as an autonomous description of the one-shot oligopolistic interaction in general equilibrium. For this model, we show the existence of a Cournot-Nash equilibrium. As the nonequivalence, in a one-stage setting, is due to the intrinsic two-stage nature of the CournotWalras equilibrium concept, we are led to consider a two-stage reformulation of the Shapley’s model. We show that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations coincides with the set of the Markov perfect equilibrium allocations of this two-stage reformulation, thereby providing a game theoretical foundation to the Cournot-Walras equilibrium approach. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: C72, D51. ∗ We are indebted to Nick Baigent, Pierpaolo Battigalli, Francis Bloch, Johann Brunner, Dikran Dikranjan, Pradeep Dubey, Jean Gabszewicz, Marcellino Gaudenzi, Peter Hammond, Jean-Fran¸cois Mertens, Nando Prati and Myrna Wooders for their comments and suggestions. † Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche, Universit`a degli Studi di Udine, Via Tomadini 30, 33100 Udine, Italy ‡ Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche, Universit`a degli Studi di Udine, Via Tomadini 30, 33100 Udine, Italy § Department of Economics, University of Warwick, Coventry CV4 7AL, United Kingdom.

1

1

Introduction

One of the first attempts to extend the analysis of oligopolistic interaction proposed by Cournot to a general equilibrium framework was due to Gabszewicz and Vial (1972), who introduced the concept of Cournot-Walras equilibrium. They considered an economy with production where firms are assumed to be “few” whereas consumers are assumed to be “many.” Firms produce consumption goods and distribute them, according to some preassigned shares, to consumers, who are therefore endowed with their initial endowments plus the bundles of consumption goods which they receive as shareholders of the firms. Consumers are then allowed to exchange their endowments among themselves and the equilibrium prices resulting from these exchanges enable firms to determine the profits associated with their production decisions. A Cournot-Walras equilibrium is a noncooperative equilibrium of a game where the players are the firms, the strategies are their production decisions and the payoffs are their profits. The denomination of this equilibrium concept comes from the fact that firms behave “`a la Cournot” in making their production decisions while consumers behave “`a la Walras” in exchanging goods. The line of research initiated by Gabszewicz and Vial (1972) raised some theoretical problems (see also Roberts and Sonnenschein (1977), Roberts (1980), Mas-Colell (1982), Dierker and Grodal (1986), among others). Gabszewicz and Vial (1972) were already aware that their concept of Cournot-Walras equilibrium depends on the rule chosen to normalize prices and that profit maximization may not be a rational objective for the firms. In order to overcome these problems, Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991) introduced a Cournot-Walras equilibrium concept for exchange economies where “few” traders, called the oligopolists, behave strategically “`a la Cournot” in making their supply decisions and share the endowment of a particular commodity while “many small” traders behave “`a la Walras” and share the endowments of all the other commodities. The oligopolists are allowed to supply a fraction of their initial endowments. Taking prices as given, each oligopolist is able to determine the income corresponding to his supply decision and to choose the bundle of commodities which gives him the highest utility. All traders, behaving “`a la Walras,” are then allowed to exchange commodities among themselves until prices clear all the markets. A Cournot-Walras equilibrium is a noncooperative equilibrium of a game where the players are the oligopolists, the strategies are their supply decisions and 2

the payoffs are the utility levels they achieve through the exchange. The line of research initiated by Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991) circumvented the theoretical difficulties mentioned above by defining an equilibrium concept which does not depend on price normalization and by replacing profit maximization with utility maximization (see also Codognato and Gabszewicz (1993), Codognato (1995), d’Aspremont et al. (1997), Gabszewicz and Michel (1997), Shitovitz (1997), Lahmandi-Ayed (2001), among others). Nevertheless, the whole Cournot-Walras equilibrium approach is not immune to another fundamental criticism. In fact, all the models mentioned above do not explain why a particular agent has a strategic behavior or a competitive one. A first attempt to provide a foundation of agents’ behavior within the cooperative approach to oligopoly was made Shitovitz (1973). Okuno et al. (1980) aimed at extending Shitovitz’s contribution to a noncooperative setting. To this end, they considered the Cournot-Nash equilibria of a model of simultaneous, noncooperative exchange between large traders, represented as atoms, and small traders, represented by an atomless sector. The model they used belongs to a line of research initiated by Shapley and Shubik (1977) (see also Dubey and Shubik (1977), Postlewaite and Schmeidler (1978), MasColell (1982), Amir et al. (1990), Peck et al. (1992), Dubey and Shapley (1994), among others). For Okuno et al. (1980), it is crucial to show that their approach is immune from a counterintuitive issue present in the cooperative context analyzed by Shitovitz (1973). In fact, this author’s Theorem B indicates that, if there are two large traders with the same endowments and preferences but not necessarily the same size, then the core and the competitive allocations coincide. In contrast to this result, Okuno et al. (1980) provided an example and a proposition showing that the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations of a mixed exchange economy satisfying the assumptions of Shitovitz’s Theorem B are not Walrasian. However, their model can be criticized for being too particular to provide a foundation of oligopoly in a general equilibrium framework, since it considers only two commodities, which no trader is allowed to simultaneously buy and sell. In this paper, we generalize the analysis of Okuno et al. (1980) by considering the Cournot-Nash equilibria of a mixed version of a model of noncooperative exchange, originally proposed by Lloyd S. Shapley, and further analyzed by Sahi and Yao (1989), for exchange economies with a finite number of traders, and by Codognato and Ghosal (2000), for exchange economies with an atomless continuum of traders. In this model, traders send out bids, 3

i.e., quantity signals, which indicate how much of each commodity they are willing to offer for trade. Every bid of each commodity is tagged by the name of some other commodity for which it has to be exchanged. The rule of price formation requires that a single price system, which equates the value of the total amount of bids of any commodity to the value of the total amount available of that commodity, is used to clear the markets. We propose an example and a proposition showing that, within this framework, the small traders always behave `a la Walras and the large traders do not lose their market power even when the core turns out to be Walrasian. As a consequence, we make clear that this model provides a foundation of the oligopolistc behavior in a general equilibrium setting, since the strategic and the competitive behavior arise endogenously. By comparing, in mixed markets, a more specific version of the Shapley’s model with the model in Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991), Codognato (1995) already showed, through an example, that the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations does not coincide with the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations. There could be two reasons for this result. The first is that the Cournot-Walras equilibrium concept has an intrinsic twostage nature, which cannot be reconciled with the one-stage Cournot-Nash equilibrium of the Shapley’s model. The second is that, in the model by Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991), the oligopolists behave `a la Cournot in making their supply decisions and `a la Walras in exchanging commodities whereas, in the mixed version of the Shapley’s model, the large traders behave unambigously `a la Cournot. This “twofold behavior” of large traders raises a further problem in the line of research introduced by Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991), which should be dealt with. In this paper, we do so by using a respecification `a la Cournot-Walras of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model, originally introduced by Busetto and Codognato (2002). In particular, we assume that large traders behave `a la Cournot in making bids, as in the Shapley’s model, while the atomless sector is assumed to behave `a la Walras. Given the atoms’ bids, prices adjust to equate the aggregate net bids to the aggregate net demands of the atomless sector. Each nonatomic trader then obtains his Walrasian demand whereas each large trader obtains final holdings determined as in the Shapley’s model. A Cournot-Walras equilibrium is a noncooperative equilibrium of a game where the players are the large traders, the strategies are their bids and the payoffs are the utility levels they achieve through the exchange 4

process described above. We show, through an example, that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations of our variant of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model does not coincide with the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations of the mixed version of the original Shapley’s model. This confirms, within a more general framework, the result obtained by Codognato (1995). Since now large traders behave unambigously `a la Cournot in both models, we are lead to believe that this nonequivalence result in a one-stage setting is explained by the two-stage implicit nature of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium concept. The nonequivalence result makes also clear that, in a one-stage framework, the mixed version of the Shapley’s model is immune to the criticism by Okuno et al. (1980). This model emerges as an autonomous description of the one-shot oligopolistic interaction in a general equilibrium framework, since even its closest Cournot-Walras variant may generate different equilibria. For this model, we show the existence of a Cournot-Nash equilibrium. Then, we proceed to check if an equivalence result can be obtained in a two-stage setting. To this end, we consider a two-stage reformulation of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model, where the atoms move in the first stage and the atomless sector moves in the second stage. Busetto and Codognato (2002) showed that any Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocation corresponds to a subgame perfect equilibrium allocation of the game just sketched. But the converse of this result does not hold since, at a subgame perfect equilibrium, the subgames associated with the atoms’ strategies leading to the same aggregate bids may be played in different ways. In this paper, we overcome this problem by adapting to our framework the notion of Markov perfect equilibrium, a subgame perfect equilibrium characterized by the fact that all players use strategies depending only on payoffs-relevant past events. We show that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations coincides with the set of the Markov perfect equilibrium allocations of the two-stage game outlined above. This theorem strengthens the result obtained by Busetto and Codognato (2002). It reconciles the line of research initiated by Shapley and Shubik (1977) with the Cournot-Walras approach and makes this approach immune to the criticism by Okuno et al. (1980), by providing it with a game-theoretical foundation of strategic and competitive behavior. This paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we provide the mathematical setting. In Section 3, we introduce our mixed version of the Shapley’s 5

model and show the existence of Cournot-Nash equilibria. In Section 4, we introduce the respecification `a la Cournot-Walras of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model and the related Cournot-Walras equilibrium concept. In Section 5, we compare the Cournot-Nash and the Cournot-Walras equilibrium concepts. In Section 6, we show the equivalence between the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations and the set of the Markov perfect equilibrium allocations. In Section 7, we conclude.

2

The mathematical model

We consider an exchange economy in which traders are represented by the elements of the set T = T0 ∪ T1 , where T0 = [0, 1] and T1 = {2, . . . , m + 1}. If a, b ∈ T0 satisfy a ≤ b, let us write [a, b) = ∅ if a = b and [a, b) = {x ∈ T0 : a ≤ x < b} if a < b. Then, it is well known that the collection S0 = {[a, b) : a, b ∈ T0 and a ≤ b} is a semiring. Let S1 = P(T1 ) be the collection of all subsets of T1 . It is also well known that this collection is an algebra. We shall denote by µ0 and µ1 , respectively, the Lebesgue measure on S0 and the counting measure on S1 . The following proposition provides us with a first characterization of the set of traders as a measure space. Proposition 1. The triplet (T, S, µ), where T is the set of traders, S = {E ⊂ T : E = A ∪ B, A ∈ S0 , B ∈ S1 }, µ : S → [0, ∞] is a set function such that, µ(E) = µ0 (E ∩ T0 ) + µ1 (E ∩ T1 ), for each E ∈ S, is a measure space. Proof. Since S0 is a semiring and S1 is an algebra, it easily follows that S is a semiring. Now, observe that µ(∅) = µ0 (∅) + µ1 (∅) = 0. Moreover, let {En } be a disjoint sequence of S with ∪∞ n=1 En ∈ S. Then, we have ∞ ∞ µ(∪∞ n=1 En ) = µ0 ((∪n=1 En ) ∩ T0 ) + µ1 ((∪n=1 En ) ∩ T1 ) ∞ = µ0 (∪∞ n=1 (En ∩ T0 )) + µ1 (∪n=1 (En ∩ T1 ))

= =

∞ X

µ0 (En ∩ T0 ) +

n=1 ∞ X

∞ X

µ1 (En ∩ T1 )

n=1

(µ0 (En ∩ T0 ) + µ1 (En ∩ T1 )) =

n=1

∞ X n=1

6

µ(En ).

Hence, µ is a measure on S. Let µ∗ denote the Caratheodory extension of µ. Since µ∗ (T ) = 1 + m < ∞, the measure space (T, S, µ) is finite and this implies that a subset E of T is µmeasurable if and only if µ∗ (E)+µ∗ (E c ) = µ∗ (T ). Denote by T the collection of all µ-measurable subsets of T . The following proposition provides us with a characterization of the set of traders as a complete measure space. Proposition 2. The triplet (T, T , µ∗ ) is a complete measure space and µ∗ is the unique extension of µ on a measure on T . Proof. It follows from the Caratheodory Extension Procedure Theorem (see Aliprantis and Border (1994), p. 289), since the measure space (T, S, µ), being finite, is σ-finite. Now, consider the triplet (T0 , S0 , µ0 ) which, as is well known, is a measure space. Denote by µ∗0 the Caratheodory extension of µ0 and by T0 the collection of all µ0 -measurable subsets of T0 . Then, it is well known that the triplet (T0 , T0 , µ∗0 ) is a complete measure space and that µ∗0 is the unique extension of µ0 to a measure on T0 . Let TT0 = {E ∩ T0 : E ∈ T } be the restriction of T to T0 . The following proposition characterizes the restriction of the measure space (T, T , µ∗ ) to T0 . Proposition 3. The triplet (T0 , TT0 , µ∗ ) is a measure space such that TT0 = T0 and µ∗ = µ∗0 , when these measures are restricted to TT0 . Proof. First, we shall show that, for every subset E of T0 , µ∗ (E) = µ∗0 (E). This can be done as follows µ∗ (E) = inf{

∞ X

µ(En ) : {En } ⊂ S, E ⊆ ∪∞ n=1 En }

n=1

= inf{ = inf{

∞ X n=1 ∞ X

µ0 (En ∩ T0 ) +

∞ X

µ1 (En ∩ T1 ) : {En } ⊂ S, E ⊆ ∪∞ n=1 En }

n=1

µ0 (En ∩ T0 ) : {En } ⊂ S, {En ∩ T1 } = ∅, E ⊂ ∪∞ n=1 (En ∩ T0 )}

n=1

= µ∗0 (E). Now, observe that, since T0 is µ-measurable, TT0 is a collection of µ-measurable subsets of T0 . Let E be a subset of T0 . By the σ-subadditivity of µ∗ , we have µ∗ (T ) ≤ µ∗ (E) + µ∗ (E c ) = µ∗ (E) + µ∗ ((E c ∩ T0 ) ∪ T1 ) ≤ µ∗ (E) + µ∗ (E c ∩ T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ). 7

On the other hand, since E is µ0 -measurable, we have µ∗ (E) + µ∗ (E c ∩ T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ) = µ∗0 (E) + µ∗0 (E c ∩ T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ) = µ∗0 (T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ) = µ∗ (T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ) = µ∗ (T ). This implies that µ∗ (E) + µ∗ (E c ) = µ∗ (T ), which, in turn, implies that E is µ-measurable, thereby showing that T0 ⊆ TT0 . Now, let E be a subset of TT0 . Since E is µ-measurable, we have µ∗ (E) + µ∗ (E c ) = µ∗ (T ). By the σ-additivity of µ∗ on T , it follows that µ∗ (E) + µ∗ (E c ∩ T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ) = µ∗ (T0 ) + µ∗ (T1 ). Therefore, we have µ∗0 (E) + µ∗0 (E c ∩ T0 ) = µ∗0 (T0 ) and this, in turn, implies that E is µ0 -measurable, thereby showing that TT0 ⊆ T0 . Hence, TT0 = T0 . Now, consider the triplet (T1 , S1 , µ1 ). It is easy to show that µ∗1 = µ1 , where µ∗1 denotes the Caratheodory extension of µ1 , and that S1 is the collection of all µ1 -measurable subsets of T1 . This implies that the triplet (T1 , S1 , µ1 ) is a complete measure space. Let TT1 = {E ∩ T1 : E ∈ T } be the restriction of T to T1 . The following proposition characterizes the restriction of the measure space (T, T , µ∗ ) to T1 . Proposition 4. The triplet (T1 , TT1 , µ∗ ) is a measure space such that TT1 = S1 and µ∗ = µ1 , where these measures are restricted to TT1 . Proof. First, by the same argument used in the proof of Proposition 3, it is possible to show that, for every subset E of T1 , µ∗ (E) = µ∗1 (E) = µ1 (E). Now, observe that, since S ⊆ T , S1 = S ∩ T1 ⊆ T ∩ T1 = TT1 . On the other hand, TT1 ⊆ P(T1 ) = S1 . Hence, S1 = TT1 . The following definition introduces the concept of an atom of a measure space (see Aliprantis and Border (1994), p. 303). Definition 1. Let (X, Σ, µ) be a measure space. A measurable set A is called an atom if µ∗ (A) > 0 and, for every subset B of A, either µ∗ (B) = 0 or µ∗ (A \ B) = 0. If (X, Σ, µ) has no atoms, then it is called an atomless measure space. If there exists a countable set A such that, for each a ∈ A, 8

the singleton set {a} is measurable with µ∗ ({a}) > 0 and µ∗ (X \ A) = 0, then the measure space (X, Σ, µ) is called purely atomic. From now on, to simplify the notation, µ∗ , µ∗0 , µ∗1 will be denoted by µ, µ0 , µ1 , respectively. The space of traders will be denoted by the complete measure space (T, T , µ). By Propositions 3 and 4, it is straightforward to show that the measure space (T0 , TT0 , µ) is atomless and that the measure space (T1 , TT1 , µ) is purely atomic. Moreover, it is clear, for each t ∈ T1 , the singleton set {t} is an atom of the measure space (T, T , µ). A null set of traders is a set of Lebesgue measure 0. Null sets of traders are systematically ignored throughout the paper. Thus, a statement asserted for “all” traders, or “each” trader, or “each” trader in a certain set is to be understood to hold for all such traders except possibly for a null set of traders. The word “integrable” is to be understood in the sense of Lebesgue. Given any function g defined on T , we denote by 0 g and 1 g the restriction of g to T0 and T1 , respectively. Analogously, given any correspondence G defined on T , we denote by 0 G and 1 G the restriction of G to T0 and T1 , respectively. The following proposition reminds us that the integrability of g is equivalent to the integrability of 0 g and 1 g. Proposition 5. A function g : T → R is integrable if and only if 0 g and 1 g are integrable over T0 and T1 , respectively. Proof. See Theorem 4 and Problem 6 in Kolmogorov and Fomin (1975), p. 298 and p. 302, respectively. R

R

R

Moreover, it is Rwell known that RT g(t) dµ = T0R0 g(t) dµ + T1 1 g(t) dµ, where R 0 Pm+1 0 1 1 t=2 g(t), by T0 g(t) dµ = T0 g(t) dµ0 and T1 g(t) dµ = T1 g(t) dµ1 = l Propositions 3 and 4. A commodity bundle is a point in R+ . An assignment l (of commodity bundles to traders) is an integrable function x: T → R+ . There is a fixed initial assignment w, satisfying the following assumption. Assumption 1. w(t) > 0, for all t ∈ T ,

R T0

w(t) dµ À 0. R

R

An allocation is an assignment x for which T x(t) dµ = T w(t) dµ. The preferences of each trader t ∈ T are described by an utility function ut : l → R, satisfying the following assumptions. R+ l → R is continuous and strictly monotonic, for all Assumption 2. ut : R+ t ∈ T , quasi-concave, for all t ∈ T0 , and concave, for all t ∈ T1 .

9

l Assumption 3. u : T × R+ → R, given by u(t, x) = ut (x), is measurable. l A price vector is a vector p ∈ R+ . According to Aumann (1966), we l define, for each p ∈ R+ , a correspondence ∆p : T → P(Rl ) such that, for each l t ∈ T , ∆p (t) = {x ∈ R+ : px ≤ pw(t)}, a correspondence Γp : T → P(Rl ) l such that, for each t ∈ T , Γp (t) = {x ∈ R+ : for all y ∈ ∆p (t), ut (x) ≥ ut (y)}, and finally a correspondence Xp : T → P(Rl ) such that, for each t ∈ T , Xp (t) = ∆p (t) ∩ Γp (t). A Walras equilibrium is a pair (p∗ , x∗ ), consisting of a price vector p∗ and an allocation x∗ , such that, for all t ∈ T , x∗ (t) ∈ Xp∗ (t). The following proposition shows that there is a measurable selector from the correspondence 0 Xp . l Proposition 6. Under Assumptions 1, 2, and 3, for each p ∈ R++ , there l exists an integrable function 0 xp : T0 → R+ such that, for each t ∈ T0 , 0 xp (t) ∈ 0 Xp (t). l Proof. First, observe that, for each p ∈ R++ , Assumption 2 implies that, 0 for each t ∈ T0 , Xp (t) 6= ∅. Moreover, from Aumann (1966), we know that the correspondence 0 Xp is Borel measurable since the correspondences 0 ∆p and 0 Γp are Borel measurable and {(t, x) : x ∈ 0 Xp (t)} = {(t, x) : x ∈ 0 ∆p (t)} ∩ {(t, x) : x ∈ 0 Γp (t)}. Finally, 0 Xp is integrably bounded

Pl

i

pj wj (t)

, i = 1, . . . , l, for all t ∈ T0 and for all x such that because x ≤ j=1pi 0 x ∈ Xp (t). But then, by Theorem 2 in Aumann (1965), there exists an integrable function 0 xp such that, for each t ∈ T0 , 0 xp (t) ∈ 0 Xp (t).

3

Cournot-Nash equilibrium

We proceed now to formulate the concept of Cournot-Nash equilibrium, considering a mixed version of the model first proposed by Lloyd S. Shapley and further analyzed by Sahi and Yao (1989) in the case of exchange 2 economies with a finite number of traders. Let b ∈ Rl be a vector such that b = (b11 , b12 , . . . , bll−1 , bll ). A strategy correspondence is a correspondence 2 2 B : T → P(Rl ) such that, for each t ∈ T , B(t) = {b ∈ Rl : bij ≥ 0, i, j = Pl 1, . . . , l; j=1 bij ≤ wi (t), i = 1, . . . , l}. A strategy selection is an integrable 2 function b : T → Rl , such that, for all t ∈ T , b(t) ∈ B(t). For each t ∈ T , bij (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l, is the amount of commodity i that trader t offers in

10

exchange for commodity j. R Given a strategy selection b, we define the ag¯ as B ¯ = ( T bij (t) dµ). Moreover, we denote by b \ b(t) a gregate matrix B strategy selection obtained by replacing b(t) in b with b(t) ∈ B(t). Then, consider the following definitions (see Sahi and Yao (1989)). Definition 2. A nonnegative square matrix A is said to be irreducible if, for every pair i, j, with i 6= j, there is a positive integer k = k(i, j) such that (k) (k) aij > 0, where aij denotes the ij-th entry of the k-th power Ak of A. Definition 3. Given a strategy selection b, a price vector p is market clearing if l , p ∈ R++

l X

l X

¯ ij = pj ( pi b

i=1

¯ ji ), j = 1, . . . , l. b

(1)

i=1

By Lemma 1 in Sahi and Yao (1989), there is a unique, up to a scalar multiple, ¯ is irreducible. Denote by p(b) price vector p satisfying (1) if and only if B ¯ is the function which associates, to each strategy selection b such that B irreducible, the unique, up to a scalar multiple, market clearing price vector p. Given a strategy selection b such that p is market clearing and unique, up to a scalar multiple, consider the assignment determined as follows: xj (t, b(t), p(b)) = wj (t) −

l X i=1

bji (t) +

l X i=1

bij (t)

pi (b) , pj (b)

for all t ∈ T , j = 1, . . . , l. It is easy to verify that this assignment is an allocation. Given a strategy selection b, the traders’ final holdings are xj (t) = xj (t, b(t), p(b)) if p is market clearing and unique, xj (t) = wj (t)otherwise, for all t ∈ T , j = 1, . . . , l. This respecification of the Shapley’s model allows us to define the following concept of Cournot-Nash equilibrium for exchange economies with a continuum of traders (see Codognato and Ghosal (2000)). ¯ ˆ such that B ˆ is irreducible is a CournotDefinition 4. A strategy selection b Nash equilibrium if ˆ ˆ ≥ ut (x(t, b(t), p(b ˆ \ b(t)))), ut (x(t, b(t), p(b)))

11

for all t ∈ T and for all b(t) ∈ B(t). The model just described allows us to deal with some basic issues concerning the analysis of noncooperative oligopoly in large economies. Okuno et al. (1980) criticized the Cournot-Walras approach to oligopoly in general equilibrium, initiated by Gabszewicz and Vial (1972), since it does not explain why a particular agent has a strategic behavior or a competitive one. Taking inspiration from the cooperative approach to oligopoly in general equilibrium introduced by Shitovitz (1973), they proposed a foundation of agents’ behavior which considers the Cournot-Nash equilibria of a model of simultaneous, noncooperative exchange between large traders, represented as atoms, and small traders, represented by an atomless sector. Their model is actually a special case of the Shapley’s model we have introduced in this section, in that only two commodities are considered and no trader is allowed to simultaneously buy and sell them. For Okuno et al. (1980), it is crucial to show that their approach is immune from a counterintuitive issue present in the cooperative context analyzed by Shitovitz (1973). In fact, they provide an example and a proposition showing that the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations of a mixed exchange economy in which atoms have the same endowments and preferences, but not necessarily the same size, are not Walrasian, whereas Theorem B in Shitovitz (1973) proves that, in this case, the core and the competitive allocations coincide. Since Codognato and Ghosal (2000) show an equivalence `a la Aumann (see Aumann (1964)) between the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations and the set of the Walras equilibrium allocations for the Shapley’s model with an atomless continuum of traders, it is crucial to check that, according to Okuno et al. (1980), it does not hold under the assumptions of Theorem B in Shitovitz (1973). We provide here a proposition and an example which clarify that the version of the Shapley’s model introduced in this section is a well-founded model of oligopoly, since the small traders always have a price-taking, Walrasian behavior, whereas the large traders keep market power even in those circumstances where the core outcome is competitive. ¯ is irreducible and Proposition 7. For each strategy selection b such that B for each t ∈ T0 , (i) p(b) = p(b \ b(t)), for all b(t) ∈ B(t); (ii) x(t, b(t), p(b \ b(t))) ∈ Xp(b) (t), for all b(t) ∈ argmax{ut (x(t, b(t), p(b \ b(t)))) : b(t) ∈ B(t)}. Proof. (i) It is an immediate consequence of Definition 2. (ii) It can be 12

proved by the same argument used in the proof of part (i) of Theorem 2 in Codognato and Ghosal (2000). Example 1. Consider the following specification of an exchange economy satisfying Assumptions 1, 2, and 3, where l = 2, T1 = {2, 3}, T0 = [0, 1], w(t) = (1, 0), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ T1 , w(t) = (1, 0), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ [0, 21 ], w(t) = (0, 1), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ [ 21 , 1]. For this economy, there is a Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocation which does not correspond to any Walras equilibrium. Proof. The only symmetric Cournot-Nash equilibrium is the strategy se√ 1+ 13 ˆ ˆ ˆ ˆ lection b, where b12 (2) = b12 (3) = 12 , b12 (t) = 21 , for all t ∈ [0, 12 ], ˆ 21 (t) = 1 for all t ∈ [ 1 , 1], which generates the allocation x b ˜1 (2) = x ˜1 (3) = 2 2 √ √ 11+ 13 1+ √ 13 ,x ˜2 (2) = x ˜2 (3) = 20+8 ,x ˜1 (t) = 12 , x ˜2 (t) = 10+43√13 , for all t ∈ [0, 12 ], 12 13 √

x ˜1 (t) = 5+26 13 , x ˜2 (t) = 12 , for all t ∈ [ 12 , 1]. On the other hand, the only Walras equilibrium of the economy considered is the pair (x∗ , p∗ ), where 1 1 x∗1 (2) = x∗1 (3) = 21 , x∗2 (2) = x∗2 (3) = 10 , x∗1 (t) = 21 , x∗2 (t) = 10 , for all 1 5 1 1 1 ∗1 ∗2 ∗ t ∈ [0, 2 ], x (t) = 2 , x (t) = 2 , for all t ∈ [ 2 , 1], p = 5 .

4

Cournot-Walras equilibrium

We proceed now to formulate the concept of Cournot-Walras equilibrium, using the respecification `a la Cournot-Walras of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model originally introduced by Busetto and Codognato (2002). In order to simplify the description of the model, we need the following restriction of Assumption 2. l Assumption 20 . ut : R+ → R is continuous and strictly monotonic, for all t ∈ T , quasi-concave, for all t ∈ T0 , and concave, for all t ∈ T1 . l This assumption allows us to define, for each p ∈ R++ , a function 0 x(·, p) : l T0 → R + , such that, for each t ∈ T0 , 0 x(t, p) = 0 ∆p (t) ∩ 0 Γp (t). We are now able to show the following proposition.

Proposition 8. Under Assumptions 1, 2, and 3, the function 0 x(·, p) is l . integrable, for each p ∈ R++ Proof. It is an immediate consequence of Proposition 6, since, for each l , 0 x(t, p) = 0 Xp (t), for all t ∈ T0 . p ∈ R++ 13

2

Let e ∈ Rl be a vector such that e = (e11 , e12 , . . . , ell−1 , ell ). A strategy 2 correspondence is a correspondence E : T1 → P(Rl ) such that, for each t ∈ P 2 T1 , E(t) = {e ∈ Rl : eij ≥ 0, i, j = 1, . . . , l; lj=1 eij ≤ wi (t), i = 1, . . . , l}. 2 A strategy selection is an integrable function e : T1 → Rl such that, for all t ∈ T1 , e(t) ∈ E(t). For each t ∈ T1 , eij (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l, is the amount of commodity i that trader t offers in exchange for commodity j. Let E be the set of all strategy selections. Moreover, let e \ e(t) be a strategy selection obtained by replacing e(t) in e with e(t) ∈ E(t). Finally, let π(e) denote the correspondence which associates, to each e ∈ E, the set of the price vectors such that Z

0 j T0

x (t, p) dµ +

l Z X i=1 T1

eij (t) dµ

Z l Z X pi j w (t) dµ + eji (t) dµ, = pj T0 i=1 T1

(2)

l j = 1, . . . , l. We assume that, for each e ∈ E, π(e) 6= ∅ and π(e) ⊂ R++ . A price selection p(e) is a function which associates, to each e ∈R E, a price R vector p ∈ π(e) and is such that p(e0 ) = p(e00 ) if T1 e0 (t) dµ = T1 e00 (t) dµ. l For each strategy selection e ∈ E, let 1 x(·, e(·), p(e)) : T1 → R+ denote a function such that 1 j

x (t, e(t), p(e)) = wj (t) −

l X i=1

eji (t) +

l X i=1

eij (t)

pi (e) , pj (e)

(3)

for all t ∈ T1 , j = 1, . . . , l. Given a strategy selection e ∈ E, taking into account the structure of the traders’ measure space, Proposition 8, and Equation (3), it is straightforward to show that the function x(t) such that x(t) = 0 x(t, p(e)), for all t ∈ T0 , and x(t) = 1 x(t, e(t), p(e)), for all t ∈ T1 , is an allocation. At this stage, we are able to define the concept of CournotWalras equilibrium. Definition 5. A pair (˜ e, x ˜), consisting of a strategy selection ˜ e and an allocation x ˜ such that x ˜(t) = 0 x(t, p(˜ e)), for all t ∈ T0 , and x ˜(t) = 1 x(t, ˜ e(t), p(˜ e)), for all t ∈ T1 , is a Cournot-Walras equilibrium, with respect to a price selection p(e), if ut (1 x(t, ˜ e(t), p(˜ e))) ≥ ut (1 x(t, e(t), p(˜ e \ e(t)))), for all t ∈ T1 and for all e(t) ∈ E(t). Busetto and Codognato (2002) provided an example showing that there exists an allocation corresponding to the Cournot-Walras equilibrium just defined which does not correspond to the Cournot-Walras equilibrium defined 14

by Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991). They also investigated the relationship between the concepts of Cournot-Walras and Walras equilibrium. In particular, they showed that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations coincides with the set of the Walras equilibrium allocations when strategic traders are represented by an atomless continuum of traders. The question arises whether that result still holds in the present framework, where strategic traders are represented as atoms. As already mentioned, Shitovitz (1973) showed that, counterintuitively, this may be the case if the core of an exchange economy is considered. The following example, proposed by Busetto and Codognato (2002), analyses an exchange economy with two identical atoms facing an atomless continuum of traders and shows that, in this economy, there is a Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocation which is not Walrasian. Example 2. Consider the following specification of an exchange economy satisfying Assumptions 1, 20 , and 3, where l = 2, T1 = {2, 3}, T0 = [0, 1], w(t) = (1, 0), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ T1 , w(t) = (1, 0), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ [0, 21 ], w(t) = (0, 1), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ [ 21 , 1]. For this economy, there is a Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocation which does not correspond to any Walras equilibrium. Proof. The only symmetric√Cournot-Walras equilibrium is the pair (˜ e, x ˜), √ 11+ 13 1+ 13 1 1 2 2 ˜ (2) = x ˜ (3) = 12 , x ˜ (2)√= x ˜ (3) = where ˜ e12 (2) = ˜ e12 (3) = 12 , x √ 1+ √ 13 1 3√ 1 5+2 13 1 2 1 ,x ˜ (t) = 2 , x ˜ (t) = 10+4 13 , for all t ∈ [0, 2 ], x ˜ (t) = 6 , x ˜2 (t) = 20+8 13 1 , for all t ∈ [ 12 , 1]. On the other hand, the only Walras equilibrium of 2 the economy considered is the pair (x∗ , p∗ ), where x∗1 (2) = x∗1 (3) = 21 , 1 1 x∗2 (2) = x∗2 (3) = 10 , x∗1 (t) = 12 , x∗2 (t) = 10 , for all t ∈ [0, 12 ], x∗1 (t) = 25 , 1 1 1 ∗2 ∗ x (t) = 2 , for all t ∈ [ 2 , 1], p = 5 .

5

Cournot-Nash and Cournot-Walras equilibrium

Example 1 and Proposition 7 show that, in the mixed version of the Shapley’s model, introduced in Section 3, all traders behave strategically but those belonging to the atomless sector have a negligible influence on prices. The strategic behavior of the atomless sector could consequently be interpreted 15

as a competitive behavior. On the other hand, in our version `a la CournotWalras of the Shapley’s model, introduced in Section 4, the atomless sector is supposed to behave competitively while the atoms have strategic power. Moreover, by comparing Examples 1 and 2, we can notice that there exists an allocation corresponding to a Cournot-Walras equilibrium which also corresponds to a Cournot-Nash equilibrium. Therefore, it seems to be reasonable to conjecture that the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations coincide with the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations. Surprisingly, this conjecture turns out to be false, as is shown by the following example proposed Busetto and Codognato (2002). Example 3. Consider the following specification of an exchange economy satisfying Assumptions 1, 20 , and 3, where l = 2, T1 = {2, 3}, T0 = [0, 1], w(t) = (1, 0), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ T1 , w(t) = (1, 0), ut (x) = lnx1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ [0, 21 ], w(t) = (0, 1), ut (x) = x1 + lnx2 , for all t ∈ [ 12 , 1]. For this economy, there is a Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocation which does not correspond to any Cournot-Nash equilibrium. Proof. The only symmetric Cournot-Walras equilibrium of √the economy considered is√ the pair (˜ e, x ˜), where ˜ e12 (2) = ˜ e12 (3) = −1+12 37 , x ˜1 (2) = √ −1+ √37 x ˜1 (3) = 11−12 37 , x ˜2 (2) = x ˜2 (3) = 14+4 , x ˜1 (t) = 21 , x ˜2 (t) = 7+23√37 , for 37 √

˜1 (t) = 1+26 37 , x ˜2 (t) = 7+26√37 , for all t ∈ [ 12 , 1]. On the other all t ∈ [0, 12 ], x hand, the only symmetric √ Cournot-Nash equilibrium is the strategy selection √ 1+ 13 ˆ ˆ ˆ ˆ 21 (t) = 5+2 √13 b12 (2) = b12 (3) = 12 , b12 (t) = 12 , for all t ∈ [0, 21 ], b 11+2 13 √

for all t ∈ [ 21 , 1], which generates the allocation x ˆ1 (2) = x ˆ1 (3) = 11+12 13 , √ 1+ √ 13 x ˆ2 (2) = x ˆ2 (3) = 22+4 , x ˆ1 (t) = 12 , x ˆ2 (t) = 11+23√13 , for all t ∈ [0, 12 ], 13 √ ˆ p(b)), ˆ x ˆ1 (t) = 5+26 13 , x ˆ2 (t) = 11+26√13 , for all t ∈ [ 12 , 1], where x ˆ(t) = x(t, b, for all t ∈ T . Example 3 confirms, in a more general context, the nonequivalence result obtained by Codognato (1995). By comparing the mixed version of the Shapley’s model with the mixed version of the model in Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991), this author showed, through an example, that the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations does not coincide with the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations . In this regard, it is worthwhile noticing that, in the Cournot-Walras model considered by Codognato (1995), the oligopolists behave `a la Cournot in making their supply decisions and `a 16

la Walras in exchanging commodities whereas, in the mixed version of the Shapley’s model, the large traders behave unambigously `a la Cournot. On the contrary, in both models compared by Example 3 above the large traders behave unambigously `a la Cournot. This has two main consequences. First, by removing one of the possible explanations of the nonequivalence result, namely the twofold behavior of the oligopolists in the model by Codognato and Gabszewicz (1991), Example 3 leads us to think that the most general cause of the nonequivalence must be the two-stage implicit nature of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium concept, which cannot be reconciled with the one-stage Cournot-Nash equilibrium of the Shapley’s model. At the same time, Example 3 makes clear that, in a one-stage setting, the mixed version of the Shapley’s model is a model of noncooperative oligopoly immune to the criticism by Okuno et al. (1980). This model emerges as an autonomous description of the one-shot oligopolistic interaction in a general equilibrium framework, since even its closest Cournot-Walras variant may generate different equilibria. The fact that traders’ behavior has an endogenous foundation makes it immune also from the technical problems which arise when one tries to prove the existence of equilibria in the models belonging to the line of research initiated by Gabszewicz and Vial (1972). In particular, in these models, equilibria may not exist, even in mixed strategies, since the Walras price correspondence may fail to be continuous. In this paper, we prove the existence of a Cournot-Nash equilibrium for the mixed version of the Shapley’s model. The construction of the mixed measure space of traders provided in Section 2 allows us to synthesize, in our proof, the techniques used by Sahi and Yao (1989) to show the existence of Cournot-Nash equilibria in finite exchange economies and those used to prove the existence of noncooperative equilibria in nonatomic games (see, Schmeidler (1973) and Khan (1985), among oth-

Theorem 1. Under Assumptions 1, 2, 3, and 4, there is a Cournot-Nash ˆ equilibrium b.

6

Cournot-Walras equilibrium as a Markov perfect equilibrium

Example 3 shows that, in mixed exchange economies, there is a CournotWalras equilibrium allocation which does not correspond to any CournotNash equilibrium. As this nonequivalence holds in a one-stage game, we are led to consider a multi-stage game. In particular, given that the CournotWalras equilibrium concept has an intrinsic two-stage flavor, it seems to be natural to analyze a two-stage game where the atoms move in the first stage and the atomless sector moves in the second stage, after observing the first stage atoms’ moves. In this section, we provide a theorem showing that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations coincides with the set of the Markov perfect equilibrium allocations of the game just sketched. More precisely, we consider the same mixed exchange economy as in Section 3. To this economy, we associate a two-stage game with observed actions (see Fudenberg and Tirole (1991)), which represents a sequential reformulation 2 of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model in Section 3. Let a ∈ Rl be a vector such that a = (a11 , a12 , . . . , all−1 , all ). The game is played in two stages, 0 and 1. We denote by A0 an action correspondence in stage 0, defined on T , such that A0 (t) is the singleton “do nothing,” for all t ∈ T0 , and P 2 A0 (t) = {a ∈ Rl : aij ≥ 0, i, j = 1, . . . , l; lj=1 aij ≤ wi (t), i = 1, . . . , l}, for all t ∈ T1 . We denote by A1 an action correspondence in stage 1, defined P 2 on T , such that A1 (t) = {a ∈ Rl : aij ≥ 0, i, j = 1, . . . , l; lj=1 aij ≤ wi (t), i = 1, . . . , l}, for all t ∈ T0 , and A1 (t) is the singleton “do nothing,” for all t ∈ T1 . An action selection in stage 0 is a function a0 , defined on T , such that a0 (t) ∈ A0 (t), for all t ∈ T , and 1 a0 is integrable. For each t ∈ T1 , 1 0 a (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l, is the amount of commodity i that trader t offers in exchange for commodity j. An action selection in stage 1 is a function a1 , defined on T , such that a1 (t) ∈ A1 (t), for all t ∈ T , and 0 a1 is integrable. For each t ∈ T0 , 0 a1 (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l, is the amount of commodity i that trader t offers in exchange for commodity j. Let S 0 and S 1 be the sets of all action selections in stage 0 and stage 1, respectively, and let H 0 and H 1 18

be the sets of all stage 0 and stage 1 histories, respectively, where H 0 = ∅ and H 1 = S 0 . In addition, let H 2 = S 0 × S 1 be the set of all final histories. ¯ as Given a final history h2 = (aR0 , a1 ), we define the aggregate matrix A R 0 1 1 0 ¯ = (¯ A aij ) = ( T0 aij (t) dµ + T1 a ij (t) dµ). Then, we can introduce the following definition (see Sahi and Yao (1989)). Definition 6. Given a final history h2 = (a0 , a1 ), a price vector p is market clearing if l p ∈ R++ ,

l X

l X

pi ¯ aij = pj (

i=1

¯ aji ), j = 1, . . . , l.

(4)

i=1

By Lemma 1 in Sahi and Yao (1989), there is a unique, up to a scalar multiple, ¯ is irreducible. Denote by p(h2 ) price vector p satisfying (4) if and only if A the function which associates, to each final history h2 = (a0 , a1 ) such that ¯ is irreducible, the unique, up to a scalar multiple, market clearing price A vector p. Given a final history h2 = (a0 , a1 ) such that p is market clearing and unique, up to a scalar multiple, consider the assignment determined as follows: xj (t, h2 (t), p(h2 )) = wj (t) −

l X

0 1 aji (t)

+

i=1

l X i=1

pi (h2 ) 0 1 aij (t) j 2 , p (h )

for all t ∈ T0 , (5)

xj (t, h2 (t), p(h2 )) = wj (t) −

l X

1 0 aji (t)

i=1

+

l X i=1

pi (h2 ) 1 0 aij (t) j 2 , p (h )

for all t ∈ T1 ,

j = 1, . . . , l. It is easy to verify that this assignment is an allocation. Finally, given a final history h2 = (a0 , a1 ), the traders’ final holdings are xj (t) = xj (t, h2 (t), p(h2 )) if p is market clearing and unique, (6) j

j

x (t) = w (t) otherwise, for all t ∈ T , j = 1, . . . , l. Now, we define a strategy profile, s, as a sequence of functions {s0 , s1 }, where s0 is defined on T ×H 0 and such that, given h0 ∈ H 0 , s0 (t, h0 ) ∈ A0 (t), for all t ∈ T , and s0 (·, h0 ) ∈ S 0 ; s1 is defined on T × H 1 and such that, given h1 ∈ H 1 , s1 (t, h1 ) ∈ A1 (t), for all t ∈ T , s1 (·, h1 ) ∈ S 1 . Moreover, we denote by s \ s(t, ·) = {s0 \ s0 (t, ·), s1 \ s1 (t, ·)} a strategy profile obtained by replacing s0 (t, ·) in s0 and s1 (t, ·) in s1 , respectively, with the 19

functions s0 (t, ·) and s1 (t, ·), where s0 (t, ·) : H 0 → A0 (t) and s1 (t, ·) : H 1 → A1 (t). With a little abuse of notation, given a strategy profile s, we denote by 1 s0 and 0 s1 the functions defined, respectively, on T1 and T0 , such that 1 0 s (t) = 1 a0 (t) = s0 (t, h0 ), for all t ∈ T1 , and 0 s1 (t) = 0 a1 (t) = s1 (t, h1 ), for all t ∈ T0 , with h1 = s0 (·, h0 ). In addition, given a strategy profile s, we define R R ¯ as S ¯ = (¯ the aggregate matrix S sij ) = ( T0 0 s1 ij (t) dµ + T1 1 s0 ij (t) dµ). Then, ¯ is irreducible, we denote by p(s) the given a strategy profile s such that S function obtained by replacing, in Equation (4), ¯ aij with ¯ sij , i, j = 1, . . . , l. Given a strategy profile s such that p is market clearing and unique, up to a scalar multiple, the allocation x(t, s(t), p(s)) is obtained by replacing, in (5), h2 with s and 0 a1 , 1 a0 , respectively, with 0 s1 , 1 s0 . Finally, the traders’ final holdings are determined as in (6), by replacing h2 with s. We proceed now to consider the subgame consisting of the stage 1 of the game outlined above, given the history h1 ∈ H 1 . Given a strategy profile s, the strategy selection s|h1 is a function, defined on T , such that, for each h1 ∈ H 1 , s|h1 (t) = s1 (t, h1 ), for all t ∈ T . In addition, given a history h1 ∈ H 1 ¯ 1 as S|h ¯ 1 = and a strategy profile s, weR define the aggregate matrix S|h R (¯ sij |h1 ) = ( T0 0 sij (t)|h1 dµ + T1 1 h1 ij (t) dµ). Then, given a history h1 ∈ H 1 , ¯ 1 is irreducible, we denote by p(s|h1 ) the and a strategy profile s such that S|h function obtained by replacing, in Equation (4), ¯ aij with ¯ sij |h1 , i, j = 1, . . . , l. Given a history h1 ∈ H 1 and a strategy profile s such that p is market clearing and unique, up to a scalar multiple, the allocation x(t, s|h1 (t), p(s|h1 )) is obtained by replacing, in (5), h2 by s|h1 and 0 a1 , 1 a0 , respectively, with 0 s|h1 , 1 h1 . The traders’ final holdings are determined as in (6), by replacing h2 with s|h1 . Finally, given a history h1 ∈ H 1 , we denote by s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 a strategy selection obtained by replacing s(t)|h1 in s|h1 with s(t)|h1 ∈ A1 (t). We are now able to define the concept of subgame perfect equilibrium for the two-stage game above. ¯ ˆ 1 is irreducible, for each Definition 7. A strategy profile ˆ s such that S|h h1 ∈ H 1 , is a subgame perfect equilibrium if, for all t ∈ T , ut (x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s))) ≥ ut (x(t, s(t, ·), p(ˆ s \ s(t, ·)))), for all possible functions s(t, ·), and, for each h1 ∈ H 1 , ut (x(t, ˆ s|h1 (t), p(ˆ s|h1 ))) ≥ ut (x(t, s(t)|h1 , p(ˆ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 ))), for all t ∈ T and for all s(t)|h1 ∈ A1 (t). 20

Busetto and Codognato (2002) showed that any Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocation corresponds to a subgame perfect equilibrium of the two-stage game just described. Nevertheless, the converse of this result does not hold since, at a subgame perfect equilibrium, the subgames associated with the atoms’ strategies leading to the same aggregate bids may be played in different ways. A possible way to avoid this unreasonable behavior is to consider the concept of Markov perfect equilibrium, a subgame perfect equilibrium in which all players use strategies depending only on payoff-relevant past events. We shall now define a notion of Markov perfect equilibrium which adapts to our framework the approach proposed by Fudenberg and Tirole (1991) and Maskin and Tirole (2001). To this end we define a future at stage 1 as an action selection at that stage and denote it by f 1 ∈ F 1 = S 1 . Given a history h1 ∈ H 1 and a future f 1 ∈ F 1 , let f 1 h1 denote a function, defined on T , such that f 1 h1 (t) = 0 f 1 (t), for all t ∈ T0 , and f 1 h1 (t) = 1 h1 (t), for all t ∈ T1 . Given a history h1 ∈ H 1 and a future f 1 ∈ F 1 , we define the aggregate R R 1 1 1 1 1 0 1 ¯ ¯ ¯ matrix f 1 H as f 1 H = (f 1 Hij ) = ( T0 f 1 h ij (t) dµ + T1 f 1 h ij (t) dµ). Then, ¯ 1 is irreducible, given a history h1 ∈ H 1 , and a future f 1 ∈ F 1 such that f 1 H 1 we denote by p(f 1 h ) the function obtained by replacing, in Equation (4), ¯ 1ij , i, j = 1, . . . , l. Given a history h1 ∈ H 1 and a future f 1 ∈ F 1 ¯ aij with f 1 h such that p is market clearing and unique, up to a scalar multiple, the allocation x(t, f 1 h1 (t), p(f 1 h1 )) is obtained by replacing, in (5), h2 with f 1 h1 and 0 a1 , 1 a0 , respectively, with 0f 1 h1 , 1f 1 h1 . The traders’ final holdings are determined as in (6), by replacing h2 with f 1 h1 . Let H 1 (·) denote a partition of H 1 , where H 1 (h1 ) denotes the set of stage 1 histories that are in the same 0 00 element of the partition as h1 . Given two partitions H 1 (·) and H 1 (·) such 0 00 0 00 00 that H 1 (·) 6= H 1 (·), we say that H 1 (·) is coarser than H 1 (·) (H 1 (·) is 0 00 finer than H 1 (·)) if any element of H 1 (·) is contained in some element of 0 H 1 (·). We are now able to provide the following definition. Definition 8. A partition H 1 (·) is said to be sufficient if, for all futures ¯ 1 is irreducible, f 1 ∈ F 1 such that, for each h1 ∈ H 1 , f 1 H 00

00

0

0

ut (x(t, f 1 h1 (t), p(f 1 h1 ))) = ut (x(t, f 1 h1 (t), p(f 1 h1 ))), 0

00

0

00

for all t ∈ T0 and for all h1 , h1 ∈ H 1 such that H 1 (h1 ) = H 1 (h1 ). The following proposition characterizes, in the present framework, the payoffrelevant history, that is the coarsest sufficient partition. 21

?

0

?

0

PropositionR 9. The partition H 1 (·) such that, for each h1 ∈ H 1 , H 1 (h1 ) = R 0 00 00 {h1 ∈ H 1 : T1 h1 (t) dµ = T1 h1 (t) dµ}, is the coarsest sufficient partition. ¯ 1 is irreducible, for each h1 ∈ Proof. Given a future f 1 ∈ F 1 such that f 1 H H 1 , Definition 6 implies that 00

0

0

00

ut (x(t, f 1 h1 (t), p(f 1 h1 ))) = ut (x(t, f 1 h1 (t), p(f 1 h1 ))), R

R

00

0

for all t ∈ T0 , if and only if T1 h1 (t) dµ = T1 h1 (t) dµ. But then, a partition R 00 0 0 H 1 (·) is sufficient if and only if h1 ∈ H 1 (h1 ), whenever T1 h1 (t) dµ = R 1 00 1? 1 1? T1 h (t) dµ. Therefore, H (·) is sufficient and any partition H (·) 6= H (·) ? is sufficient if and only if it is finer than H 1 (·). We are now able to define the concept of Markov perfect equilibrium. ¯ ˆ 1 is irreducible, for each Definition 9. A strategy profile ˆ s such that S|h h1 ∈ H 1 , is a Markov perfect equilibrium if, 0 00 00 ? 0 (i) for all t ∈ T , s1 (t, h1 ) = s1 (t, h1 ), whenever h1 ∈ H 1 (h1 ), and ut (x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s))) ≥ ut (x(t, s(t, ·), p(ˆ s \ s(t, ·)))), for all possible functions s(t, ·); (ii) for each h1 ∈ H 1 , ut (x(t, ˆ s|h1 (t), p(ˆ s|h1 ))) ≥ ut (x(t, s(t)|h1 , p(ˆ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 ))), for all t ∈ T and for all s(t)|h1 ∈ A1 (t). In order to prove the equivalence theorem, we need to introduce a further assumption on endowments and preferences of the atomless sector. To this end, we introduce the following preliminary definitions about graphs (see Minc (1988)). Definition 10. Let V be a nonempty n-set whose elements may be conveniently labelled 1, 2, . . . , n, and let E be a binary relation on V , that is, a set of ordered pairs of elements of V . The pair D = (V, E) is called a directed graph, the elements of V are its vertices and the elements of E are the arcs of D. The arc (i, j) is said to join vertex i to j. A sequence of arcs (i, t1 ), (t1 , t2 ), . . . , (tm−2 , tm−1 ), (tm−1 , j) in D is called a path connecting i to j. 22

Definition 11. A directed graph is said to be strongly connected if, for any ordered pair of distinct vertices, i and j, there is a path in D connecting i to j. l l We denote by L the set of commodities {1, . . . , l} and by R+j>0 ⊂ R+ the set l of vectors in R+ , whose j-th component is strictly positive. For each i ∈ L, we consider the set Ti = {t ∈ T0 : wi (t) > 0}. Clearly, by Assumption 1, µ(Ti ) > 0. We say that the commodities i, j ∈ L stand in the relation C if there is a measurable subset Ti0 of Ti , with µ(Ti0 ) > 0, such that, for each l l l trader t ∈ Ti0 , {x ∈ R+ : ut (x) = ut (y)} ⊂ R+j>0 , for all y ∈ R++ . In addition, we use the following definition provided by Codognato and Ghosal (2000), to whom we refer for further details.

Definition 12. The set of commodities L is said to be a net if {hi, ji : iCj} 6= ∅ and the directed graph DL (L, C) is strongly connected. Then, we can introduce the following assumption. Assumption 40 . The set of commodities L is a net. We are now ready to state our equivalence theorem, which is proved in the Appendix. Theorem 2. Under Assumptions 1, 20 , 3, and 40 , (i) if (˜ e, x ˜) is a CournotWalras equilibrium with respect to the price selection p(e), there is a Markov perfect equilibrium ˜ s such that x(t, p(˜ e)) = x(t, ˜ s(t), p(˜ s)), for all t ∈ T ; (ii) if ˆ s is a Markov perfect equilibrium, there are a strategy selection ˆ e and a price selection p(e) such that the pair (ˆ e, x ˆ), where x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = 0 1 x(t, p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T0 , and x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = x(t, ˆ e(t), p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T1 , is a Cournot-Walras equilibrium with respect to the price selection p(e).

7

Conclusions

The main purpose of this paper has been to provide a game-theoretical foundation to the noncooperative analysis of oligopoly in large economies. To this end, we have compared the two fundamental approaches to oligopoly in general equilibrium, that is the line of research initiated by Shapley and Shubik (1977) and the Cournot-Walras approach pioneered by Gabszewicz 23

and Vial (1972). More precisely, we have first focused on the one-stage case, by proposing two models: A mixed version of the model of noncooperative exchange originally proposed by Lloyd S. Shapley, on the one hand, and the respecification `a la Cournot-Walras of this model originally introduced by Busetto and Codognato (2002), on the other. We have provided an example showing that the set of the Cournot-Nash equilibrium allocations of the mixed version of the Shapley’s model does not coincide with the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations of its respecification. This nonequivalence result makes clear that, in a one-stage framework, the mixed version of the Shapley’s model is an independent, well-founded model of noncooperative oligopoly, where the strategic and the competitive behavior are endogenously generated. For this model, we have proved the existence of a Cournot-Nash equilibrium. As our analysis has pointed out that the nonequivalence in a one-shot setting is essentially caused by the intrinsic two-stage nature of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium concept, we have proceeded to consider a further reformulation of the Shapley’s model as a two-stage game, where the atoms move in the first stage and the atomless sector moves in the second stage. We have shown that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allocations coincides with the set of the Markov perfect equilibrium allocations of this two-stage game.

8

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 1. As in Sahi and Yao (1989), we shall first show the existence of a slightly perturbed Cournot-Nash equilibrium. Given ² > 0, we R ² ² ¯ ¯ define the aggregate bid matrix B to be B = ( T bij (t) dµ + ²). Clearly, the ¯ ² is irreducible. The interpretation is that an outside agency places matrix B fixed bids of ² for each pair of commodities (i, j). Given ² > 0, we denote by p² (b) the function which associates to each strategy selection b the unique, up to a scalar multiple, price vector which satisfies l X i=1

l X

¯ ij + ²) = pj ( pi (b

¯ ji + ²), j = 1, . . . , l. (b

(7)

i=1

ˆ ² is an ²-Cournot-Nash Definition 13. Given ² > 0, a strategy selection b equilibrium if ˆ ² (t), p² (b ˆ ² ))) ≥ ut (t, b(t), p² (b ˆ ² \ b(t)))), ut (x(t, b 24

for almost all t ∈ T and for all b(t) ∈ B(t). The following fixed point theorem, proved by Fan (1952) and Glicksberg (1952), is the basic tool we use to show Theorem 1. Theorem (Fan-Glicksberg). Let K be a nonempty, convex and compact subset of a locally convex space X. If φ is an upper semicontinuos mapping from K into K and if, for all x ∈ X, the set φ(x) is nonempty and convex, then there exists a point xˆ ∈ K such that xˆ ∈ φ(ˆ x). Neglecting, as usual, the distinction between integrable functions and equiv2 alence classes of such functions, we denote by L1 (µ, Rl ) the set of integrable 2 functions taking values in Rl and by L1 (µ, B(·)) the set of strategy selections (see Schmeidler (1973) and Khan (1985)). The locally convex space we 2 shall working in is L1 (µ, Rl ) endowed with its weak topology. The following lemma provides us with the required properties of the set L1 (µ, B(·)). Lemma 1. The set L1 (µ, B(·)) is nonempty, convex and weakly compact. P

Proof. For each i = 1, . . . , l, let λij ≥ 0, lj=1 λij = 1. Since w is an l2 assignment, the function b : T → R+ such that, for each t ∈ T , bij (t) = 2 i λij w (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l belongs to L1 (µ, B(·)). The fact that L1 (µ, Rl ) is a vector space and the fact that, for each t ∈ T , B(t) is convex imply that L1 (µ, B(·)) is convex. Finally, the weak compactness of L1 (µ, B(·)) may be R proved following Khan (1985). First, notice that supb∈L1 (µ,B(·)) T |bij | dµ < ∞, i, j = 1, . . . , l. Let ² > 0. For each j = 1, . . . , l, there exists a δj > 0 R (depending upon ²) such that | E wj (t) dµ| ≤ ², for all measurable sets E with µ(E) ≤ δj (see Problem 18.6 in Aliprantis and Burkinshaw (1990b), p. 127). This implies that, if µ(E) ≤ δ = min{δ1 , . . . , δl }, then, for all R b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), E |bij (t)| dµ ≤ ², i, j = 1, . . . , l. This, by the DunfordPettis theorem (see Diestel (1984), p. 93), in turn implies that L1 (µ, B(·)) has a weakly compact closure. Now, let {bn } be a Cauchy sequence of 2 L1 (µ, B(·)). Since L1 (µ, Rl ) is complete, {bn } converges in the mean to an integrable function b. But then, there exists a subsequence {bkn } of {bn } such that bkn → b a.e. (see Theorem 21.5 in Aliprantis and Burkinshaw (1990a), p. 159). The compactness of B(t), for each t ∈ T , implies that b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)). Hence L1 (µ, B(·)) is norm closed and, since it is also convex, it is weakly closed (see Corollary 4 in Diestel (1984), p. 12). Given ² > 0, let α : L1 (µ, B(·)) → L1 (µ, B(·)) be a mapping such that α(b) = {b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)) : b(t) ∈ αt (b), for almost all t ∈ T } where, for 25

each t ∈ T , the mapping αt : L1 (µ, B(·)) → B(t) is such that αt (b) = argmax{ut (x(t, b(t), p² (b \ b(t)))) : b(t) ∈ B(t)}. The following lemma provides us with the required properties of α. Lemma 2. Given ² > 0, the mapping α : L1 (µ, B(·)) → L1 (µ, B(·)) is an upper semicontinuous mapping such that, for all b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), the set α(b) is nonempty and convex. Proof. Let ² > 0 be given. Consider a trader t ∈ T1 . By Lemma 4 in Sahi and Yao (1989), we know that αt is an upper semicontinuos mapping such that, for all b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), αt (b) is nonempty, compact and convex. Now, consider a trader t ∈ T0 . Given b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), Proposition 7 implies that ut (x(t, b(t), p² (b \ b(t)))) = ut (x(t, b(t), p² (b))), for all b ∈ B(t). Therefore, for all b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), αt is nonempty and compact, by the continuity of the function ut (x(t, b(t), p² (b))) over the compact set B(t), and convex, by Assumption 2. The upper semicontinuity of αt is a straightforward consequence of the Maximum Theorem (see Berge (1997), p. 116). Now, given a strategy selection b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), by Proposition 6, there exists an integrable l function xp² (b) : T0 → R+ such that, for each t ∈ T0 , xp² (b) (t) ∈ Xp² (b) (t). By Lemma 5 in Codognato and Ghosal (2000), for each t ∈ T0 , there exist P λj (t) ≥ 0, lj=1 λj (t) = 1, such that xjp² (b) (t)

Pl j

= λ (t)

j=1

j

p²j (b)0 w (t) , j = 1, . . . , l. p²j (b)

l Define a function λ : T0 → R+ , such that, λ(t) = λ(t), for each t ∈ 0 T0 . Since xp² (b) and w are integrable functions with respect to µ0 and Pl ²j 0 j j=1 p (b) w (t) À 0, for all t ∈ T0 , λ is a integrable function with re∗ ∗ l2 spect to µ0 . Now, define a function 0 b : T0 → R+ such that 0 bij (t) = ∗ 0 i w (t)λj (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l, for all t ∈ T0 . The function 0 b is integrable with respect to µ0 and hence, by Proposition 3, with respect to µ. Moreover, by Theorem 2 in Codognato and Ghosal (2000), b∗ (t) ∈ αt (b), for each t ∈ T0 . ∗ ∗ l2 Let 1 b : T1 → R+ be a function such that 1 b (t) ∈ αt (b), for each t ∈ T1 . ∗ The function 1 b is integrable with respect to µ1 and hence, by Proposition 4, with respect to µ. But then, by Proposition 5, α(b) is nonempty. The convexity of α(b) is a straightforward consequence of the convexity of αt (b), for all t ∈ T . Finally, the upper semicontinuity of α may be proved following Khan

26

(1985). Since L1 (µ, B(·)) is weakly compact, we can show the upper semicontinuity of α by showing that its graph is closed in L1 (µB(·)) × L1 (µB(·)) (see the Corollary in Berge (1997), p. 112). Let {bν , b∗ν } be a net converging to (b, b∗ ) where b∗ν ∈ α(bν ). The set {bν , b∗ν } ∪ (b, b∗ ), being a subset of L1 (µ, B(·) × L1 (µ, B(·)), is relatively weakly compact (see Theorem 2.11 in Aliprantis and Border (1994), p. 30). By the Eberlein-Smulian Theorem (see Aliprantis and Border (1994), p. 200), the set {bν , b∗ν } ∪ (b, b∗ ) is also relatively weakly sequentially compact. This, in turn, implies that there exists a sequence {bn , b∗n }, extracted from the net {bν , b∗ν }, which converges weakly to (b, b∗ ) (see Problem 17L in Kelley and Namioka (1963), p. 165). Now, for each t ∈ T , denote by Ls {b∗n (t)} the set of limit points of the sequence {b∗n (t)} and by coLs {b∗n (t)} the set of convex combinations of these limit points. For each t ∈ T , the fact that αt is compact-valued and upper semicontinuous and the fact that B(t) is compact imply that Ls {b∗n (t)} ⊆ αt (b) and this, together with the fact that αt (b) is convex, in turn, implies that coLs {b∗n (t)} ⊆ αt (b). Since the sequence {b∗n } converges weakly to b∗ and is uniformly integrable (see Hildenbrand (1974), p. 52), by Proposition C in Artstein (1979), we have b∗ (t) ∈ coLs {b∗n (t)} and so we are done. Now, we can prove the existence of an ²-Cournot-Nash equilibrium. ˆ² . Lemma 3. For each ² > 0, there is an ²-Cournot-Nash equilibrium b Proof. It is a straightforward consequence of Lemmas 1 and 2 and the Fan-Glicksberg Theorem. As in Sahi and Yao (1989), we introduce the concept of δ-positivity. 2

Definition 14. For δ > 0, the function Bδ : T → Rl is a δ-positive strategy P P 2 function if Bδ (t) = B(t) ∩ {b ∈ Rl : i6∈J j∈J (bij + bji ) ≥ δ, for each J ⊆ {1, . . . , l}}, for each t ∈ T1 with w(t) À 0; Bδ (t) = B(t), for the remaining traders t ∈ T . ˆ ² is called δ-positive if, for almost all t ∈ T , An ²-Cournot-Nash equilibrium b ² δ ˆ (t) ∈ B (t). For each t ∈ T1 , let δ ∗ (t) = 1 min{w1 (t), . . . , wl (t)} and b m ∗ δ ∗ = min{δ ∗ (t) : δ ∗ (t) > 0, t ∈ T1 }. Given ² > 0, let αδ : L1 (µ, B(·) → ∗ L1 (µ, B(·)) be a mapping such that αδ (b) = {b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·) : b(t) ∈ ∗ ∗ ∗ αtδ (b), for almost all t ∈ T } where, for each t ∈ T , αtδ (b) = αt (b) ∩ Bδ (t). The following lemma is a strengthening of Lemma 4.

27

Lemma 4. For each ² > 0, there is a δ ∗ -positive ²-Cournot-Nash equilibrium ˆ² . b Proof. Let ² > 0 be given. By Lemma 6 in Sahi and Yao (1989), we ∗ know that, for each b ∈ L1 (µ, B(·)), αtδ (b) is nonempty, for each t ∈ T1 ∗ with w(t) À 0. But then, by the same argument of Lemma 4, αδ (b) is ∗ nonempty. The convexity of αδ (b) is a straightforward consequence of the ∗ convexity of αt (b) and Bδ (t), for all t ∈ T . The upper semicontinuity of ∗ αδ can be proved using the same argument as that of Lemma 4 since, for ∗ all t ∈ T , αtδ is upper semicontinuos, by the upper semicontinuity of αt and the nonemptyness and compactness of B(t) (see Theorem 2’ in Berge (1997), p. 114). This completes the proof since all the assumptions of the Fan-Glicksberg Theorem are satisfied. Let ²n = n1 , n = 1, 2, . . .. By Lemma 4, for each n = 1, 2, . . ., there is ˆ ²n . The fact that the sequence aRδ ∗ -positive ²-Cournot-Nash equilibrium b 2 0 ˆ ²n { T0 b (t) dµ0 } belongs to the compact set W = {bij ∈ Rl : 0 ≤ bij ≤ R i 1 ˆ ²n T0 w (t) dµ0 , i, j = 1, . . . , l}, the sequence { b } belongs to the compact set Q δ∗ ˆ ²n ), for each n = 1, 2, . . ., ˆ²n , where pˆ²n = p(b t∈T1 B (t) and the sequence p belongs, by Lemma 9 in Sahi and Yao (1989), to a compact set P, imR ˆ ²n (t) dµ0 , 1 b ˆ ²n , pˆ²n } belongs to the compact set plies that the sequence { T0 0 b Q ∗ W × t∈T1 Bδ (t)×P . This, in turn, implies that it has a subsequence (which we denote in the same way to save in notation) which converges to an element Q ∗ of the set W × t∈T1 Bδ (t) × P (see Problem D in Kelley (1955), p. 238). ˆ ²n } satisfies the assumptions of Theorem A in ArtSince the sequence {0 b ˆ such that 0 b(t) ˆ is a limit point of 0 b ˆ ²n (t) stein (1979), there is a function 0 b R ˆ ²n (t) dµ0 } converges for almost all t ∈ T0 and such that the sequence { T0 0 b R ∗ ˆ dµ0 . Moreover, 0 b(t) ˆ to T0 0 b(t) ∈ Bδ (t), for almost all t ∈ T0 , because 0ˆ ˆ ²n (t)}, for almost all t ∈ T0 . Since b(t) is the limit of a subsequence of {0 b ˆ ²n } converges to a point 1 b ˆ ∈ Qt∈T Bδ∗ (t), the sequence the sequence {1 b 1 R ˆ ²n (t) dµ1 } converges to R 1 b(t) ˆ dµ1 . But then, by Proposition 5, the { T1 1 b T1 R ˆ ²n (t) dµ} must converge to R b(t) ˆ dµ. Since the sequence {ˆ sequence { T b p²n } T R ˆ dµ converges to a price vector pˆ ∈ P , by the continuity of (5), pˆ and T b(t) must satisfy (1). Moreover, since, by Lemma 9 in Sahi and Yao (1989), pˆ À 0, ˆ ¯ is completely reducible. But Lemma 1 in Sahi and Yao (1989) implies that B ∗ ˆ ˆ ∈ L1 (µ, Bδ (·)), by Remark 3 in Sahi and Yao (1989), B ¯ must then, since b 28

ˆ is a δ ∗ -positive ²-Cournot-Nash be irreducible. In order to conlcude that b ˆ ˆ \ b(t)))), equilibrium, we have to show that ut (x(t, b(t), pˆ)) ≥ ut (x(t, b(t), p(b ˆ ¯ \ b(t) denote the aggregate for almost all t ∈ T and for all b(t) ∈ B(t). Let B ² ˆ ˆ \ b(t) and let B ¯ n \ b(t) dematrix corresponding to the strategy selection b ˆ ²n \ b(t), note the aggregate matrix corresponding to the strategy selection b for each n = 1, 2, . . .. As in Sahi and Yao (1989), we proceed by considering the following possible cases. ˆ ¯ \ b(t) is completely reCase 1. t ∈ T1 and b(t) ∈ B(t) is such that B ²n ˆ ¯ \ b(t) is irreducible, for each n = 1, 2, . . ., and so is ducible. Clearly, B ˆ ˆ ²n \ ¯ \ b(t), by Remark 3 in Sahi and Yao (1989). Since the sequence {RT b B R ˆ \ b(t)(t) dµ b(t)(t) dµ} converges, by the same argument given above, to T b and since, by Lemma 2 in Sahi and Yao (1989), prices are cofactors, the seˆ ²n \ b(t))} converges to p(b ˆ \ b(t)). Consequently, the sequence quence {p²n (b ²n ˆ ²n ˆ \ b(t))). The fact that {x(t, b(t), p (b \ b(t)))} converges to x(t, b(t), p(b ²n ²n ˆ ˆ the sequence {x(t, b (t), pˆ )} converges to x(t, b(t), pˆ) and the fact that ˆ ²n (t), pˆ²n )) ≥ ut (x(t, b(t), p²n (b ˆ \ b(t)))), for each n = 1, 2, . . ., allow ut (x(t, b ˆ ˆ\ us to conclude, by Assumption 2, that ut (x(t, b(t), pˆ)) ≥ ut (x(t, b(t), p(b b(t)))). ˆ ¯ \ b(t) in not completely reCase 2. t ∈ T1 and b(t) ∈ B(t) is such that B ˆ ²n (t), pˆ²n )} converges to x(t, b(t), ˆ ducible. The fact that the sequence {x(t, b pˆ) ² ² ˆ n (t), pˆ n ) ≥ ut (w(t)), for each n = 1, 2, . . ., imply, and the fact that ut (x(t, b ˆ ˆ by Assumption 2, that ut (x(t, b(t), pˆ)) ≥ ut (w(t)) = ut (x(t, b(t), p(b\b(t)))). ˆ ¯ \ b(t) is irreducible Case 3. t ∈ T0 and b(t) ∈ B(t). Clearly, the matrix B ²n ˆ ²n ²n ˆ ²n and, by Proposition 7, p (b \ b(t)) = p (b ), for each n = 1, 2, . . ., and ˆ \ b(t)) = p(b). ˆ Since b(t) ˆ is a limit point of the sequence {b ˆ ²n (t)}, it is a p(b limit of a subsequence (which we denote in the same way to save in notation) of this sequence. But then, the fact that the sequence {x(t, b(t), pˆ²n )} conˆ ²n (t), pˆ²n )} converges verges to x(t, b(t), pˆ), the fact that the sequence {x(t, b ˆ ˆ ²n (t), pˆ²n ) ≥ ut (x(t, b(t), pˆ²n )), for to x(t, b(t), pˆ) and the fact that ut (x(t, b ˆ each n = 1, 2, . . ., imply that ut (x(t, b(t), pˆ)) ≥ ut (x(t, b(t), pˆ)). This completes the proof of Theorem 1. Proof of Theorem 2. (i) Let (˜ e, x ˜) be a Cournot-Walras equilibrium with respect to the price selection p(e). Let p(h1 ) denote a function obtained by replacing, in the price selection p(e), each strategy selection e with a history h1 such that h1 (t) = e(t), for all t ∈ T1 . Consider now a history h1 ∈ H 1 . As, 29

by assumption, p(h1 ) À 0, Assumption 20 implies that p(h1 )0 x(t, p(h1 )) = p(h1 )w(t), for all t ∈ T0 . But then, by Lemma 5 in Codognato and Ghosal P (2000), for all t ∈ T0 , there exist λj ≥ 0, j = 1, . . . , l, lj=1 λj = 1, such that Pl 0 j

1

j=1

j

x (t, p(h )) = λ

pj (h1 )wj (t) , j = 1, . . . , l. pj (h1 )

l Define now a function λ : T0 → R+ such that λj (t) = λj (t), j = 1, . . . , l, for all t ∈ T0 . Let ˜ s|h1 denote a function, defined on T , such that ˜ s(t)|h1 ∈ A1 (t), j for all t ∈ T , and 0˜ sij (t)|h1 = wi (t)λ (t), i, j = 1, . . . , l, for all t ∈ T0 . It is straightforward to show that the function 0˜ s|h1 is integrable. We want now R R ¯ ˜ 1 = (¯ ˜ sij |h1 ) = ( T0 0 s1 ij (t)|h1 dµ + T1 1 h1ij (t) dµ) to show that the matrix S|h is irreducible. Let i, j ∈ L be two commodities which stand in the relation C. Consider a trader t ∈ Ti0 . First, observe that p(h1 )w(t) > 0 since, by assumption, p(h1 ) À 0. This, together with Assumption 20 , implies that 0 x(t, p(h1 )) > 0 and, given that the commodities i and j stand in the relation ¯ L |h1 = (¯ C, that 0 xj (t, p(h1 )) > 0. Consider now the matrix S sLij |h1 ) such R that ¯ sLij |h1 = Ti0 wi (t)λj (t) dµ, if iCj, and ¯ sLij |h1 = 0, otherwise. If iCj, ¯ sLij |h1 > 0, since, for each t ∈ Ti0 , wi (t) > 0 and λj (t) > 0. But then, the ¯ L ¯ ˜ 1 is irreducible as it is such that ˜ matrix S|h sij |h1 ≥ ¯ sij |h1 , i, j = 1, . . . , l, ¯ L |h1 , by Assumption 40 and by the argument used in the and the matrix S proof of Theorem 2 in Codognato and Ghosal (2000), is irreducible. As it is easy to verify that 0 j

x (t, p(h1 )) = wj (t) −

l X

˜ sji (t)|h1 +

i=1

l X

˜ sij (t)|h1

i=1

pi (h1 ) , pj (h1 )

for all t ∈ T0 , j = 1, . . . , l, and as p(h1 ) satisfies Equation (1), we have Z j

T0

+

w (t) dµ −

l Z X i=1 T1

l Z X i=1 T0

1

˜ sji (t)|h dµ +

pi (h1 ) h1ij (t) dµ j 1

p (h )

l Z X i=1 T0

Z

=

j

T0

w (t) dµ +

˜ sij (t)|h1 dµ l Z X i=1 T1

h1ji (t) dµ,

j = 1, . . . , l. This implies that l X i=1

l X

pi (h1 )¯ ˜ sij |h1 = pj (h1 )(

i=1

30

pi (h1 ) pj (h1 )

¯ ˜ sji |h1 ), j = 1, . . . , l,

and, consequently, by Equation (4), that p(h1 ) = p(˜ s|h1 ). It is then straightforward to verify that 0 xj (t, p(h1 )) = xj (t, ˜ s(t)|h1 , p(˜ s|h1 )), for all t ∈ T0 , j = 1, . . . , l, 1 xj (t, h1 (t), p(h1 )) = xj (t, ˜ s(t)|h1 , p(˜ s|h1 )), for all t ∈ T1 , j = 1, . . . , l. It remains now to show that no trader t ∈ T , in stage 1, has an advantageous deviation from ˜ s(t)|h1 . This is trivially true for all t ∈ T1 . Suppose now that there exist a trader t ∈ T0 and an action s(t)|h1 ∈ A1 (t) such that ut (x(t, s(t)|h1 , p(˜ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 ))) > ut (x(t, ˜ s(t)|h1 , p(s|h1 ))). Since, as an immediate consequence of Definition 6, p(˜ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 ) = p(˜ s|h1 ), the last inequality implies that ut (x(t, s(t)|h1 , p(h1 ))) > ut (0 x(t, p(h1 ))). As p(h1 )x(t, s(t)|h1 , p(h1 )) = p(h1 )w(t), this implies that 0 x(t, p(h1 )) 6∈ ˜ 1 be a history such that ∆p(h1 ) (t) ∩ Γp(h1 ) (t), a contradiction. Let now h ˜ 1 (t) = ˜ h e(t), for all t ∈ T1 , and let ˜ s be a strategy profile such that, for all ˜ 1 (t) and ˜ t ∈ T, ˜ s0 (t, h0 ) = h s1 (t, h1 ) = ˜ s(t)|h1 , for each h1 ∈ H 1 . Then, p(˜ e) = p(˜ s) and 0 xj (t, p(˜ e)) = xj (t, ˜ s(t), p(˜ s)), for all t ∈ T0 , j = 1, . . . , l, 1 j j x (t, ˜ e(t), p(˜ e)) = x (t, ˜ s(t), p(˜ s)), for all t ∈ T , j = 1, . . . , l. Moreover, 0 00 since p(h1 ) is a price selection, it follows that p(h1 ) = p(h1 ) whenever 00 ? 0 0 00 h1 ∈ H 1 (h1 ). This implies that, for all t ∈ T , s1 (t, h1 ) = s1 (t, h1 ), when00 ? 0 ever h1 ∈ H 1 (h1 ). It remains now to show that no trader t ∈ T has an advantageous deviation from ˜ s. As, for each trader t ∈ T0 , p(˜ s \ s(t, ·)) = 1 1 ˜1 ˜ ˜ p(˜ s|h \ s(t, h )|h ), it is straightforward consequence of the previous discussion that no trader t ∈ T0 has an advantageous deviation from ˜ s. Suppose 0 now that there exists a trader t ∈ T1 and functions s (t, ·) and s1 (t, ·) such that ut (x(t, ˜ s \ s(t, ·), p(˜ s \ s(t, ·)))) > ut (x(t, ˜ s(t), p(˜ s))). ˜ 1 \ h(t) be a history obtained by replacing h ˜ 1 (t) in h ˜ 1 with h(t) = Let h s0 (t, h0 ) and let ˜ e \ e(t) be a strategy selection obtained by replacing ˜ e(t) in 0 0 1 ˜ ˜ e by e(t) = s (t, h ). As p(˜ e \ e(t)) = p(˜ s|h \ h(t)) = p(˜ s \ s(t, ·)), the last inequality implies that ut (1 x(t, e(t), p(˜ e \ e(t)))) = ut (x(t, s(t, ·), p(˜ s \ s(t, ·)))) > 1 ut (x(t, ˜ s(t), p(˜ s))) = ut ( x(t, ˜ e(t), p(˜ e))), 31

which is a contradiction. (ii) Let ˆ s be a Markov perfect equilibrium. Consider 1 1 a history h ∈ H . First, it is straightforward to show that, for all t ∈ T0 , p(ˆ s|h1 )x(t, ˆ s|h1 (t), p(ˆ s|h1 )) = p(ˆ s|h1 )w(t). We want now to show that, for 1 1 all t ∈ T0 , x(t, ˆ s|h (t), p(ˆ s|h )) = 0 x(t, p(ˆ s|h1 )). Suppose that this is not the case for a trader t ∈ T0 . Then, by Assumption 20 , there is a bundle z ∈ {x ∈ l : p(ˆ s|h1 )x = p(ˆ s|h1 )w(t)} such that ut (z) > ut (x(t, ˆ s|h1 (t), p(ˆ s|h1 )). By R+ Lemma 5 in Codognato and Ghosal (2000), there exist λj ≥ 0, j = 1, . . . , l, Pl j j=1 λ = 1, such that Pl j

z =λ

j

j=1

pj (ˆ s|h1 )wj (t) , j = 1, . . . , l. pj (ˆ s|h1 )

Let sij (t) = wi (t)λj , i, j = 1, . . . , l. Since, as an immediate consequence of Definition 6, p(ˆ s|h1 ) = p(ˆ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 ), it is easy to verify that z j = xj (t, s(t), p(ˆ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 )), j = 1, . . . , l. But then, we have ut (x(t, s(t), p(ˆ s|h1 \ s(t)|h1 ))) = ut (z) > ut (x(t, ˆ s|h1 (t), p(ˆ s|h1 ))), a contradiction. As the function x(·, h1 (·), p(ˆ s|h1 )) is an allocation, we then obtain that Z T0

0 j

x (t, p(ˆ s|h )) dµ +

Z j

T0

1

w (t) dµ +

l Z X i=1 T1

l Z X i=1 T1

h1ij (t) dµ

pi (ˆ s|h1 ) = pj (ˆ s|h1 )

(8)

h1ji (t) dµ.

Let now p(e) be a function which associates, to each e, the price vector p(ˆ s|h1 ), where h1 is such that h1 (t) = e(t), for all t ∈ T1 . First, let us 0 notice that, since ˆ s is a RMarkov perfect equilibrium, we have p(ˆ s|h1 ) = R R 00 0 00 p(ˆ s|h1 ) if T1 h1 (t) dµ = T1 h1 (t) dµ and then p(e0 ) = p(e00 ), if T1 e0 (t) dµ = R 00 1 T1 e (t) dµ. Moreover, if we replace, in Equation (8), the history h with a strategy selection e such that e(t) = h1 (t), for all t ∈ T1 , and the price p(ˆ s|h1 ) with the price p(e), it follows immediately that the function p(e) satisfies Equation (1). Therefore, we can conclude that p(e) is a price selection. It also follows immediately from the above argument that, for each history h1 ∈ H 1 , 32

x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = 0 x(t, p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T0 , and x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = 1 x(t, ˆ e(t), p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T1 , where e is a strategy selection such that e(t) = 1 ˆ 1 be a history such that h ˆ 1 (t) = ˆ h (t), for all t ∈ T1 . Let now h s0 (t, h0 ), 1 ˆ (t), for all for all t ∈ T , and let ˆ e be a strategy selection such that ˆ e(t) = h 1 0 ˆ t ∈ T1 . As p(ˆ s) = p(ˆ s|h ), x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = x(t, p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T0 , and x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = 1 x(t, ˆ e(t), p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T1 . But then, in order to show that the pair (ˆ e, x ˆ), where x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = 0 x(t, p(ˆ e)), 1 for all t ∈ T0 , and x ˆ(t) = x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s)) = x(t, ˆ e(t), p(ˆ e)), for all t ∈ T1 , is a Cournot-Walras equilibrium with respect to the price selection p(e), it remains to show that no trader t ∈ T1 has an advantageous deviation from the strategy selection ˆ e. Suppose, on the contrary, that there exists a trader t ∈ T1 and a strategy e(t) ∈ E(t) such that ut (1 x(t, e(t), p(ˆ e \ e(t)))) > ut (1 x(t, ˆ e(t), p(ˆ e))). ˆ 1 \ h(t) be a history obtained by replacing h ˆ 1 (t) in h ˆ 1 with h(t) = e(t) Let h and let ˆ s \ s(t) be a strategy profile obtained by replacing ˆ s0 (t, ·) in ˆ s0 with ˆ 1 \ h(t)) = p(ˆ s0 (t) = h(t). As p(ˆ s \ s(t)) = p(ˆ s|h e \ e(t)), the last inequality implies that ut (1 x(t, s(t), p(ˆ s \ s(t)))) = ut (1 x(t, e(t), p(ˆ e \ e(t)))) > 1 1 ut ( x(t, ˆ e(t), p(ˆ e))) = ut ( x(t, ˆ s(t), p(ˆ s))), which is a contradiction. This completes the proof of Theorem 2.

References [1] Aliprantis C.D., Border K.C. (1994), Infinite dimensional analysis, Springer, New York. [2] Aliprantis C.D., Burkinshaw O. (1990a), Principles of real analysis, Academic Press, Boston. [3] Aliprantis C.D., Burkinshaw O. (1990b), Problems in real analysis, Academic Press, Boston. [4] Amir R., Sahi S., Shubik M., Yao S. (1990), “A strategic market game with complete markets,” Journal of Economic Theory 51, 126-143. 33

[5] Artstein Z. (1979), “A note on Fatou’s lemma in several dimensions,” Journal of Mathematical Economics 6, 277-282. [6] Aumann R.J. (1964), “Markets with a continuum of traders,” Econometrica 32, 39-50. [7] Aumann R.J. (1965), “Integrals of set valued functions,” Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications 12, 1-12. [8] Aumann R.J. (1966), “Existence of competitive equilibria in markets with a continuum of traders,” Econometrica 24, 1-17. [9] Berge C. (1997), Topological spaces, Dover, New York. [10] Busetto F., Codognato G. (2002), “Cournot-Walras equilibrium as a subgame perfect equilibrium,” Discussion Paper No. 2002-1, CEPET (Central European Porgram in Economic Theory), Institute of Public Economics, Graz University. [11] Codognato G. (1995), “Cournot-Walras and Cournot equilibria in mixed markets: a comparison,” Economic Theory 5, 361-370. [12] Codognato G., Gabszewicz J.J. (1991), “Equilibres de Cournot-Walras dans une ´economie d’´echange,” Revue Economique 42, 1013-1026. [13] Codognato G., Gabszewicz J.J. (1993), “Cournot-Walras equilibria in markets with a continuum of traders,” Economic Theory 3, 453-464. [14] Codognato G., Ghosal S. (2000), “Cournot-Nash equilibria in limit exchange economies with complete markets and consistent prices,” Journal of Mathematical Economics 34, 39-53. [15] d’Aspremont C., Dos Santos Ferreira R., G´erard-Varet L.-A. (1997), “General equilibrium concepts under imperfect competition: a Cournotian approach,” Journal of Economic Theory 73, 199-230. [16] Dierker H., Grodal B. (1986), “Nonexistence of Cournot-Walras equilibrium in a general equilibrium model with two oligopolists,” in Hildenbrand W., Mas-Colell A. (eds), Contributions to mathematical economics in honor of G´erard Debreu, North-Holland, Amsterdam. 34

[17] Diestel J. (1984), Sequences and series in Banach spaces, Springer, New York. [18] Dubey P., Shapley L.S. (1994), “Noncooperative general exchange with a continuum of traders: two models, ” Journal of Mathematical Economics 23, 253-293. [19] Dubey P., Shubik M. (1978), “The noncooperative equilibria of a closed trading economy with market supply and bidding strategies,” Journal of Economic Theory 17, 1-20. [20] Fan K. (1952), “Fixed points and minimax theorems concerning sets with convex sections,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the U.S.A. 38, 121-126. [21] Fudenberg D., Tirole J. (1991), Game theory, MIT Press, Cambridge Mass.. [22] Gabszewicz J.J., Michel P. (1997), “Oligopoly equilibrium in exchange economies,” in Eaton B.C., Harris R. G. (eds), Trade, technology and economics. Essays in honour of Richard G. Lipsey, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. [23] Gabszewicz J.J., Vial J.-P. (1972), “Oligopoly ‘`a la Cournot-Walras’ in a general equilibrium analysis,” Journal of Economic Theory 4, 381-400. [24] Glicksberg I.L. (1952), “A further generalization of Kakutani fixed point theorem with applications to Nash equilibrium points,” Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 3, 170-174. [25] Halmos P.R. (1974), Measure theory, Springer, New York. [26] Hildenbrand W. (1974), Core and equilibria of a large economy, Princeton University Press, Princeton. [27] Kelley J.L. (1955), General Topology, Van Nostrand, New York. [28] Kelley J.L., Namioka I. (1963), Linear topological spaces, Springer, New York.

35

[29] Khan M.A. (1985), “On extensions of the Cournot-Nash theorem,” in Aliprantis C.D., Burkinshaw O., Rothman N.J. (eds), Advances in equilbrium theory, Springer, New York. [30] Kolmogorov A.N., Fomin S.V. (1975), Introductory real analysis, Dover, New York. [31] Lahmandi-Ayed R. (2001), “Oligopoly equilibria in exchange economies: a limit theorem,” Economic Theory 17, 665-674. [32] Mas-Colell A. (1982) “The Cournotian foundations of Walrasian equilibrium theory,” in Hildenbrand W. (ed), Advances in economic theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. [33] Maskin E., Tirole J. (2001), “Markov perfect equilibrium,” Journal of Economic Theory 100, 191-219. [34] Minc H. (1988), Nonnegative matrices, Wiley, New York. [35] Okuno M., Postlewaite A., Roberts J. (1980), “Oligopoly and competition in large markets,” American Economic Review 70, 22-31. [36] Peck J., Shell K., Spear S.E. (1992), “The market game: existence and structure of equilibrium,” Journal of Mathematical Economics 21, 271299. [37] Postlewaite A., Schmeidler D. (1978), “Approximate efficiency of nonWalrasian Nash equilibria,” Econometrica 46, 127-137. [38] Roberts D.J., Sonnenschein H. (1977), “On the foundations of the theory of monopolistic competition,” Econometrica 45, 101-114. [39] Roberts K. (1980), “The limit points of monopolistic competition,” Journal of Economic Theory 22, 256-278. [40] Sahi S., Yao S. (1989), “The noncooperative equilibria of a trading economy with complete markets and consistent prices,” Journal of Mathematical Economics 18, 325-346. [41] Schmeidler D. (1973), “Equilibrium points of nonatomic games,” Journal of Statistical Physics 7, 295-300. 36

[42] Shapley L.S., Shubik M. (1977), “Trade using one commodity as a means of payment,” Journal of Political Economy 85, 937-968. [43] Shitovitz B. (1973), “Oligopoly in markets with a continuum of traders,” Econometrica 41, 467-501. [44] Shitovitz B. (1997), “A comparison between the core and the monopoly solutions in a mixed exchange economy,” Economic Theory 10, 559-563

37

On Noncooperative Oligopoly in Large Economies∗

We show that the set of the Cournot-Walras equilibrium allo- cations coincides with the set of the Markov perfect equilibrium allocations of the two-stage game outlined above. This theorem strengthens the result obtained by Busetto and Codognato (2002). It reconciles the line of research initiated by Shapley and Shubik ...

266KB Sizes 1 Downloads 56 Views

Recommend Documents

Noncooperative Oligopoly in Markets with a Cobb ...
solutions in theoretical models, Cobb-Douglas utility functions will turn out ..... an auxiliary game, which we call Γ1, where only the atoms act strategically,.

Pairwise stable matching in large economies
Hour: 17.10. Date: November, 30th (Thursday) 2017. Place: Room: 5C, building C, SGH. Pairwise stable matching in large economies. Michael Greinecker. University of Graz. Abstract: This paper provides a model of stable pairwise matchings in two-sided

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Dynamic Economies - Core
Mar 5, 2014 - operator maps a probability distribution into a probability distribution, so its domain or range is not a lattice in any natural order (Hopenhayn and ...... 13A natural first approach to comparative statics in general equilibrium econom

On Competitive Cycles in Productive Economies
II%: into 53, _ It is homogeneous of degree 1. It is smooth on the interior ..... and using the homogeneity of degree zero of F;i and FL ..... associates to (( Y, c1), a).

Oligopoly Strategy.pdf
Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. Oligopoly Strategy.pdf. Oligopoly Strategy.pdf. Open. Extract.

Inequality Constraints in Recursive Economies
Sep 6, 2007 - The following definition of time iteration will be used.7 ... As far as the author is aware, there has been no application of “time .... The final proposition will show that the sequence of policy functions .... without markedly incre

Optimization in Economies with Nonconvexities
Abstract. Nonconvex optimization is becoming the fashion to solve constrained optimization problems. Classical Lagrangian does not necessarily represent a ...

Robust Noncooperative Spectrum Sharing Game in ...
Aug 25, 2017 - ter/receiver pairs are in competition for the use of the same bandwidth .... and noise plus aggregate interference power spectral density (PSD).

Profit sharing and strike activity in Cournot oligopoly - Springer Link
Feb 27, 1998 - employment level or other forms of pay like workers' participation schemes. .... a Call to strike concerns only one establishment b Monthly ...... bosch, Center for Operations Research and Econometrics, Catholic University.

Profit sharing and strike activity in Cournot oligopoly - Springer Link
Feb 27, 1998 - to increase its market share, its profits, and its workers' pay (see Bensa'id et al., 1990; Bensa'/d and Gary-Bobo, ... to substitute the profit share for the base wage. Also, empirical inves- tigations made ..... our bargaining proble

oligopoly experiments in the current millennium - Wiley Online Library
OLIGOPOLY EXPERIMENTS IN THE CURRENT. MILLENNIUM. Jan Potters and Sigrid Suetens. Tilburg University, CentER, TILEC. Abstract. We present a general overview of papers that employ laboratory experiments to study oligopoly markets. We focus on papers t

corporate governance problems in transition economies - CiteSeerX
different ways that owners maintain control over the work of management: 1) the owners directly .... initiatives in the field of corporate governance. Comparative ...

Optimal Taxation in Life-Cycle Economies - ScienceDirect
May 31, 2002 - System Macro Meeting in Cleveland, as well as James Bullard and Kevin Lansing ... Key Words: optimal taxation; uniform taxation; life cycle.

A systematic study on parameter correlations in large ...
Abstract. Although much work has been done on duplicate document detection (DDD) ..... Thus we believe that the size of each piece can not be too large,.

Investor's Information Sharing with Firms in Oligopoly
Apr 14, 2015 - the investor uses a public channel to transmit information, the investor does not reveal .... Of course, the firms can use a mixed strategy.

Parameter optimization in 3D reconstruction on a large ...
Feb 20, 2007 - File replication allows a single file to be replicated to multiple storage ... Data are then replicated from that SE to other two SEs and so on.

Special issue on “Energy Efficiency in Large-Scale ... - Elsevier
As large-scale distributed systems - such as Grids, Clouds and P2P networks - gather and share more and more computing nodes and storage resources, their energy consumption is exponentially increasing. While much effort is nowadays put into hardware

Special issue on “Energy Efficiency in Large-Scale ... - Elsevier
“green” solutions. We invite submissions on the topics including, but not limited to: Energy-efficient Grid, Cloud, and Data-center technology. Energy efficiency ...

The Effects of Global Shocks on Small Commodity-Exporting Economies
207. American Economic Journal: Macroeconomics 2014, 6(2): 207–237 ..... measured by real GDP, industrial production, volume of exports and imports, plus the ..... versus US expenditures and sectoral output) are fairly robust to this impact ...

Oligopoly (Notes) 2.pdf
Sign in. Loading… Whoops! There was a problem loading more pages. Retrying... Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying.

A Primer on Canonical Monetary Economies 1 ...
ct = nt,. Ms t+1 = At+1,. Bd t = 0. • Optimization conditions. – Firms: Pt = Wt. – Households .... However, holding currency overnight does provide liquidity services.

The Effects of Global Shocks on Small Commodity-Exporting Economies
Lessons from Canada†. By Valery ..... With regard to Table 2, the main lesson to be drawn is that the business cycle statistics of the ...... Computer and electronic.