On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53 Kai F. Wehmeier

I supply a semantics and a tableaux calculus for a rstorder logic based on Hintikka's strongly exclusive interpretation of the variables, and prove that the calculus is sound and complete with respect to the semantics. abstract.

1 Introduction. In Tractatus 5.53, Wittgenstein, with characteristic brevity, proposes a notational convention that is intended to make the identity symbol superuous in logical languages:

Identity of the object I express by identity of the sign and not by means of a sign of identity. Dierence of the objects by dierence of the signs. As it stands, the convention is ambiguous.

Hintikka (1956) suggests two

ways in which it might be interpreted; he refers to these as the `weakly' and `strongly exclusive interpretations of the variables,' respectively:



weakly exclusive:

From the range of a bound variable all objects are

excluded that are values of variables occurring free within the scope of the associated quantier.



strongly exclusive:

From the range of a bound variable all objects

are excluded that are values of variables in whose scope the subformula governed by the associated quantier occurs (where the scope of a bound variable is the scope of the quantier that binds it, and the scope of a free variable is the entire formula in which it occurs free). In 5.531 through 5.5321, Wittgenstein proceeds to show how the contents of various formulas in Russellian notation can be rendered in a language employing the convention of 5.53. explains that Russell's

In particular, in 5.5321 Wittgenstein

∀x(F x → x = a) may be rewritten as (∃xF x → F a)∧

342

Kai F. Wehmeier

¬∃x∃y(F x ∧ F y).

As Hintikka (1956), p.230, observes, this example shows

that Wittgenstein cannot have had the strongly exclusive interpretation in mind.

For, under the strongly exclusive reading, the Wittgensteinian

formula says that, if anything other than there are no two objects

F.

x

and

y,

a

is

F,

a is also F , and that a, and both satisfying

then

both distinct from

This would be true in a two-element domain in which both elements

satisfy the predicate Under

the

F.

moniker

`Wittgensteinian

predicate

logic',

I

have

dis-

cussed the weakly exclusive interpretation in Wehmeier (2004) and in Wehmeier (2008); it shall not detain us further. While not Wittgenstein's intended convention, Hintikka's strongly exclusive reading is interesting in its own right, but also because Frank Ramsey appears to have misinterpreted Tractatus 5.53 as proposing such a reading. On November 11, 1923, Ramsey writes to Wittgenstein:

Have you noticed the diculty in expressing without = what Russell expresses by

∃x(F x ∧ x 6= a)? 1

After Wittgenstein supplies the formula

(F a → ∃x∃y(F x ∧ F y)) ∧ (¬F a → ∃xF x) , Ramsey sheepishly replies on December 27, 1923:

I didn't think there was a real diculty about ∃x(F x ∧ x 6= a), i.e., that it was an objection to your theory of identity, but I didn't see how to express it, because I was under the silly delusion that if an x and an a occurred in the same proposition the x could not take the value a. 2 Two points about this exchange seem remarkable. First, no matter whether one adopts the strongly or the weakly exclusive interpretation, Ramsey's troublesome formula can be rewritten simply as

∃x ((F a ∨ ¬F a) → F x), so Ramsey should have been able to nd an appropriate rendition even while under his `silly delusion.' Second, the `silly delusion' appears to be exactly Hintikka's strongly exclusive interpretation: No matter where in a formula a free variable

a occurs,

its value is excluded from the range of all bound variables occurring in the same formula. In the following, I will thus refer to a rst-order logical system using the strongly exclusive interpretation of the variables as Ramsey

predicate logic or simply R-logic . In what follows, I develop a model-theoretic semantics for R-logic, show its mutual interpretability with ordinary rst-order logic with identity

=

(FOL ), and provide a tableaux calculus, for which proofs of soundness and completeness are sketched.

1 Wittgenstein (1995), p.191. 2 Wittgenstein (1995), p.194.

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53

343

2 The Syntax and Semantics of R-Logic. The language

L

of rst-order logic (FOL), as understood here, has the

following primitive symbols. 1. the propositional connectives 2. the quantier symbols



and

¬, ∧, ∨, → ∃

3. countably many bound individual variables 4. countably many free individual variables 5. for each positive integer

n,

x, y, x1 , x2 , . . .

a, b, a1 , a2 , . . .

countably many

n-ary

predicate symbols

P n , Qn , Rn , P1n , P2n , . . . L-formulas are strings of the form Ra1 . . . an , where R is an n-ary ai are free variables. If A and B are L-formulas, then so are ¬A, A ∧ B , A ∨ B , and A → B . If F [a] is an L-formula in which x does not occur, then ∀xF [x] and ∃xF [x] are also L-formulas. The 3 language of R-logic is L. = = The language L of rst-order logic with identity (FOL ) arises from L by the addition of a designated binary predicate symbol =. Its formulas Atomic

predicate symbol and the

are constructed just like those of R-logic, except that there is the additional binary predicate symbol

=

available.

A sentence is a formula without occurrences of free variables.

U

U together with an n-ary relation n-ary predicate symbol R of L. When considering U as a = structure for FOL , the additional predicate symbol = is to be interpreted as true identity on U . A U -assignment is a mapping ν from the individual variables into U . A structure

RU

over

U

is a non-empty domain

for each

Before I give the ocial denition of the semantics for R-logic, let me illustrate one of its peculiarities. From the range of a bound variable we are to omit the values of all variables in whose scope the associated quantier occurs, where the scope of a free variable is the entire formula in which it

P a∧∀xP x. The bound x occurs within the scope of the free variable a, and hence its range must not include the value assigned to a. If, on the other hand, we consider ∀xP x not as a subformula of a larger context, but as a formula in its own right, the bound variable x does not occur within the scope of any other

occurs free. By way of example, consider the formula variable

variable, and should hence range over the entire domain. This means that when we break down

P a∧∀xP x into components for the purpose of semantic

3 In matters of syntax, we are largely following Schütte (1977), especially in the use of typographically distinguished free variables and of the theory of nominal forms.

344

Kai F. Wehmeier

evaluation, we must memorize the fact that the right conjunct originally occurred within the scope of

a,

or else we will interpret its bound variable

incorrectly. In R-logic, the range of a bound variable thus depends on the context of the associated quantier's occurrence within the formula, and it is this feature of R-logic that necessitates a somewhat more cumbersome semantic apparatus than those of either

FOL=

or W-logic.

U be a structure with non-empty domain U . We regard every element u of U as a constant symbol with denotation u (i.e., we use elements Now let

from the domain as autonymous constants, again following Schütte 1977). The

L(U)-sentences

arise from the

rence of a free variable for

L= (U)-sentences).

a

L-formulas

by replacing every occur-

with a constant symbol

u∈U

(and analogously

Alternatively, we may describe the

L(U)-sentences L by the

as the closed formulas of the rst-order language obtained from

u, as an additional primitive symbol, for u ∈ U (and similarly for the L= (U)-sentences). If ν is a U = ν assignment, and A is an L-formula (or an L -formula), then A is the result of replacing every individual variable a in A by the individual constant ν(a). addition of an individual constant each element

The semantics to be dened below is new in the sense that Hintikka (1956) only provides rules by means of which the quantiers of R-logic can be successively eliminated in favor of standard quantiers and the identity symbol, but does not specify an independent semantics for R-logic. We rst dene the relation

U , relative to a nite set V

of R-truth of an L(U)-sentence in a structure U (these will represent the objects

of elements of

excluded from the range of bound variables). 1.

U hRu1 . . . un , V i

2.

U h¬A, V i

3.

U hA ∧ B, V i

i

i

hu1 , . . . , un i ∈ RU

U 6 hA, V i i

U hA, V i

and

U hB, V i,

and similarly for the

other Boolean connectives 4.

U h∀xF [x], V i

i for every

u ∈ U \ V , U hF [u], V ∪ {u}i

5.

U h∃xF [x], V i

i for some

u ∈ U \ V , U hF [u], V ∪ {u}i

L(U)-sentence A, we dene U A to mean U hA, V i, where U that occur as constants in A. Since every Lsentence is an L(U)-sentence, we have thus dened R-truth of L-sentences in structures U generally: An L-sentence A is R-true in U i U hA, ∅i; It is R-valid if it is R-true in every structure U . If S is a set of L-sentences, and F an L-sentence, we say that F is an R-consequence of S if every structure U in which every element of S is R-true also makes F R-true. Given an Given an

V

is the set of elements of

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53

345

L-formula A and a variable assignment ν , we say that A is R-true in U ν = under ν if U A . Standard Tarskian truth |= of L (U)-sentences in U is dened as usual.

3 Interpreting R-Logic in FOL= Our rst aim is to show that to every

L= -sentence ψ(A)

L-sentence A there corresponds an U , U A i U |= ψ(A), i.e.,

such that, for all structures

that R-logic is interpretable in

FOL= .

Hintikka (1956), pp.229-231, achieves this by providing rules for rewriting R-logic quantiers by means of standard quantiers and identity; A given

L-formula

is successively transformed, by application of these rules, into

formulas containing both Ramseyan and standard quantiers, as well as identity, until all Ramseyan quantiers have disappeared.

Our recursive

translation avoids passing through such mixed formulas and must thus, for reasons explained in the preceding section, make an additional book-keeping eort with respect to free variables. We rst dene a binary translation function

L-formula A

and a nite set

1. For atomic formulas

V

ψ,

taking as arguments an

of free variables.

A, ψ(A, V ) := A.

2.

ψ(¬A, V ) := ¬ψ(A, V )

3.

ψ(A∧B, V ) := ψ(A, V )∧ψ(B, V ), and similarly for the other Boolean connectives

4.

 V ψ(∀xF [x], V ) := ∀x b∈V x 6= b → ψ(F [x], V ∪ {x}) , where ψ(F [x], V ∪ {x}) is short for ψ(F [a], V ∪ {a})xa , i.e., the result of replacing a with x in ψ(F [a], V ∪ {a}), where a is a fresh (neither in ∀xF [x] nor in V ) free variable.

5.

ψ(∃xF [x], V ) := ∃x

V

b∈V

x 6= b ∧ ψ(F [x], V ∪ {x})



By abuse of language, we also dene a unary translation function

L-formula A, ψ(A) := ψ(A, FV(A)), where FV(A) set of free variables occurring in A. We write ν[V ] for the image of V the mapping ν , i.e., ν[V ] = {ν(a) : a ∈ V }. follows: For any

U be a structure, let V be a nite set of U -assignment, and let A be an L-formula. Then

Lemma 1 Let

be a

U hAν , ν[V ]i ⇔ U |= ψ(A, V )ν .

ψ

as

is the under

free variables, let

ν

346

Kai F. Wehmeier

The proof of the lemma proceeds by induction on the formula

A.

The atomic

case is trivial, as are the inductive cases involving the Boolean connectives. It remains to consider the quantier cases; We discuss only the universal

A is of the form ∀xF [x]. Then U h∀xF [x]ν , ν[V ]i a u ∈ U \ ν[V ], U hF [u]ν , ν[V ] ∪ {u}i, i.e., U hF [a]νu , νua [V ∪ a {a}]i, where νu is just like ν except that it maps a to u, a being a fresh quantier. Suppose that

i for every

free variable.

By the induction hypothesis, this is the case i for every a

u ∈ U \ ν[V ], U |= ψ(F [a], V ∪ {a})νu . Since a is not in V , this holds i ν a V a 6= b → ψ(F [a], V ∪ {a}) u . This, however, is for all u ∈ U , U |= b∈V  V x ν equivalent to U |= ∀x b∈V x 6= b → ψ(F [a], V ∪ {a})a , q.e.d. Corollary 1 (Interpretability of R-logic in

L-formulas A, all U Aν ⇔ U |= ψ(A)ν .

1. For all

2. For all

L-sentences A

structures

U,

and all

and all structures

FOL= ) U -assignments ν ,

U , U A ⇔ U |= ψ(A).

V is FV(A), and part 2 follows L-sentences A, Aν is the same expression as

Part 1 is the special case of lemma 1 where from part 1 by noting that for

A.

4 Interpreting FOL= in R-Logic In this section, we will establish a converse to corollary 1, that is, we will

FOL=

show that

can be interpreted in R-logic.

There are two main dierences between our translation and the one proposed by Hintikka (1956). First, in the quantier case, Hintikka's translation procedure requires a prior rewriting of the formula to be translated into a particular normal form (schema (6) in Hintikka 1956, pp.231-232), which our translation does without.

Second, the need for book-keeping of free

variables involved in our translation manifests itself in Hintikka's procedure through the requirement that, for the purpose of translating a formula

F,

all rewritings of quantiers are to be imagined as taking place inside the

F

context of

(so that variables free in

F

but absent in quantied subformu-

las are still recognized as constraining the range of the subformulas' bound variables). We rst dene a binary translation function sentences

A

and nite sets

V

φ,

taking as arguments

L= -

of free variables, as follows:

a and b are distinct free variables, φ(a = b, V ) := ⊥(a, b), ⊥(a, b) is some propositional contradiction in precisely the two free variables a and b (say Rab∧¬Rab, for some binary relation symbol R).

1. Where where

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53 2.

φ(a = a, V ) := >(a),

where

>(a) a

in precisely the one free variable predicate symbol

347

is some propositional tautology

P a ∨ ¬P a,

(say

for some unary

P ).

3.

φ(A, V ) := A

4.

φ(¬A, V ) := ¬φ(A, V )

5.

φ(A ∧ B, V ) := φ(A, V ) ∧ φ(B, V ), and similarly for the other Boolean

for all other atomic formulas

A.

connectives. 6.

V φ(∀xF [x], V ) := ∀xφ(F [x], V ∪ {x}) ∧ b∈V φ(F [b], V ), where φ(F [x], V ∪ {x}) is short for φ(F [a], V ∪ {a})xa , a being a fresh free variable.

7.

φ(∃xF [x], V ) := ∃xφ(F [x], V ∪ {x}) ∨

W

b∈V

φ stand for φ(A) := φ(A, FV(A)).

By abuse of language, we also let tion dened as follows:

A FV(A),

Lemma 2 Let

be an

including

let

1-1

on

V.

U

L= -formula,

let

V

φ(F [b], V )

the unary translation func-

be a nite set of free variables

be a structure, and let

ν

be a

U -assignment

that is

Then

U |= Aν ⇔ U φ(A, V )ν . The proof proceeds by induction on the formula

A.

Only two cases are

of interest.

a = b, with distinct free variables a and {a, b}. Also U 6 ⊥(a, b)ν . Second, suppose A is of the form ∀xF [x] (the existential case is analν ν ogous). We have U |= ∀xF [x] i for every u ∈ U , U |= F [u] , i.e., for a νu all u ∈ U , U |= F [a] , where a is a fresh free variable. This in turn is First, suppose

b. U 6|= (a = b)ν ,

A

is of the form

because

ν

is

1-1

on

equivalent to: (*) For every a νu .

a

u ∈ U \ ν[V ], U |= F [a]νu ;

and for every

u ∈ ν[V ],

U |= F [a]

By the induction hypothesis, the rst conjunct in (*) holds i for every a

u ∈ U \ν[V ], U φ(F [a], V ∪{a})νu , i.e., i U φ(∀xF [x], V )ν . The second ν conjunct of (*) holds i for every b ∈ V , U |= F [b] , and hence by induction V ν hypothesis i U b∈V φ(F [b], V ) . Putting things together, we see that ν (*) is equivalent to U φ(∀xF [x], V ) , q.e.d.

348

Kai F. Wehmeier

Corollary 2 (Interpretability of

FOL=

in R-Logic)

L= -formulas A, all structures U , and 1-1 on FV(A), U |= Aν i U φ(A)ν .

1. For all are

2. For all

L= -sentences A

and all structures

all

U -assignments ν

U , U |= A

i

that

U φ(A).

Part 1 is an immediate consequence of the lemma, and part 2 follows from part 1 by noting that every variable assignment is set of free variables, and that for sentences

A, Aν

1-1

on the empty

is the same expression as

A.

5 A Tableaux Calculus for R-Logic Before we embark on the presentation of our tableaux calculus, it is perhaps appropriate to discuss briey the calculus suggested by in Hintikka (1956) pp.235-236, for the system sketched there for the strongly exclusive interpretation (i.e., R-logic) appears to be unsound. In order to see this, it is helpful to review some of Hintikka's apparatus, since his calculus is rather unlike any of those in use today. tive rules are framed in terms of a metalogical relation among called equivalence, which we shall write

⇔.

The deduc-

L-formulas

This relation is by stipulation

L-formulas equivalent in the sense of ⇔ are considered inter⇒ is dened as follows: A ⇒ B i A ⇔ A ∧ B . An L-formula A is said to be provable if ¬A ⇒ A and refutable if A ⇒ ¬A. Hintikka's rule (11)(c) (p.235) tells us that ∀xP x ⇒ P y , i.e., that ∀xP x ⇔ ∀xP x ∧ P y . So the L-formulas on the left and on the right are transitive, and

changeable in all contexts. A consequence relation

interchangeable irrespective of context; in particular, then,

(∗) ∀xP x ∧ ¬P y ⇔ (∀xP x ∧ P y) ∧ ¬P y. (∗) is tautologically equivalent to the L-formula (∀xP x ∧ ¬P y) ∧ ¬(∀xP x ∧ ¬P y) and also contains the same free variables

The right hand side of

as the latter; hence by Hintikka's rule (9), we obtain

(∗∗) From

(∗)

(∀xP x ∧ P y) ∧ ¬P y ⇔ (∀xP x ∧ ¬P y) ∧ ¬(∀xP x ∧ ¬P y). and

(∗∗)

it follows by the transitivity of



that

∀xP x ∧ ¬P y ⇔ (∀xP x ∧ ¬P y) ∧ ¬(∀xP x ∧ ¬P y) from which, by denition of

⇒,

we obtain

∀xP x ∧ ¬P y ⇒ ¬(∀xP x ∧ ¬P y),

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53 i.e., that

∀xP x∧¬P y

is refutable. This

says that everything other than

y

is

P,

349

L-formula, however, is satisable (it and y itself isn't P ). An analogous

result holds for provability instead of refutability: In Hintikka's calculus, the 4

L-formula ∀xP x → P y

is provable , yet it is not R-valid on any reasonable

denition of validity for R-logic (it fails to hold, for instance, in any oneelement domain where

P

is interpreted by the empty set, and

y

is assigned

the sole member of the domain as its value). If the preceding argument is correct and Hintikka's calculus is indeed unsound for R-logic, then our tableaux system constitutes the rst sound and complete proof procedure for R-logic. While the tableaux calculus introduced below is in many ways similar to the Boolos-Burgess calculus of Boolos (1984) for

FOL

and to the W-

procedure of Wehmeier (2008) for Wittgensteinian predicate logic, there is one obvious dierence. The need for keeping tabs on free variables, which manifested itself already in the semantics for R-logic, also necessitates the

hA, V i of L-formulas A and nite sets V L-formulas. Note that in the context of tableaux, it is always understood that hA, V i is a pair consisting of an L-formula A and a set V of free variables, whereas in the context of the semantics, A is taken to be an L(U)-formula and V a subset of the domain of U . Given a U -assignment ν , there is of course an obvious correspondence

labeling of tableaux with pairs

of free variables, rather than just

between the two notions. The tableaux rules can be given schematically as follows (add as many of the usual propositional rules as you like). 1. Closure:

h¬P, V i hP, W i × where

P

is any atomic

L-formula.

2. Double Negation:

h¬¬A, V i hA, V i 4 One can show generally that, if A is refutable, ¬A is provable. We've just seen that ∀xP x ∧ ¬P y is refutable, hence its negation, which is tautologically equivalent to ∀xP x → P y , is provable.

350

Kai F. Wehmeier

3. Conditional:

hA → B, V i h¬A, V i|hB, V i 4. Negated Conditional:

h¬(A → B), V i hA, V i h¬B, V i 5. Negated Universal:

h¬∀xF [x], V i h∃x¬F [x], V i 6. Negated Existential:

h¬∃xF [x], V i h∀x¬F [x], V i 7. Universal Instantiation:

h∀xF [x], V i hF [a], V ∪ {a}i where

a

is a free variable that does not occur in

(a) there is a pair that

a ∈ W,

(b) for all pairs

hB, W i

F , a 6∈ V ,

and either

on the branch under consideration such

or

hB, W i

on the branch under consideration,

W = ∅.5

8. Existential Instantiation:

h∃xF [x], V i hF [b1 ], V ∪ {b1 }i| . . . |hF [bk ], V ∪ {bk }i|hF [a], V ∪ {a}i 5 It is possible that there is no free variable a not occurring in F and V even if case (2) doesn't obtain (viz., if all the elements of free-variable sets on the branch are also in V ). In such a situation, universal instantiation is not applicable.

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53

351

S is the union of all sets W such that hB, W i occurs on the branch under consideration, then {b1 , . . . , bk } = S \ V , and the free variable a is new to the branch under consideration (i.e., for any hB, W i on the branch, a does not occur in B and a 6∈ W ). with the following proviso: If some pair

We say that a branch in a tableau is closed if it contains pairs

h¬P, W i, where P

is atomic and

V

and

W

A

if all its branches are closed. A tableau for

h¬A, FV(A)i.

A closed tableau for

A

hP, V i and

are arbitrary. A tableau is closed is a tableau beginning with

is also called a proof of

A.

6 Soundness Let

U

be a structure, let

variables, let

S

A

L-formula, let V be a nite set of free hB, W i where B is an L-formula and W a

be an

be a set of pairs

nite set of free variables. We make the following denitions. 1. The pair is

1-1

on

hA, V i is R-satisable V , U hAν , ν[V ]i.

L-formula A

2. The

in

U

is R-satisable in

if for some

U

if

U -assignment ν

hA, FV(A)i

that

is.

S is simultaneously R-satisable if there is a U -assignment ν S 1-1 on {W : for some L-formula B, hB, W i ∈ S} and such U hB ν , ν[W ]i for every hB, W i ∈ S .

3. The set that is that 4. Let

T

L-formulas. Then T {hB, FV(B)i : B ∈ T } is.

be a set of

if the set

is simultaneously R-satisable

5. A branch in a tableau is simultaneously R-satisable if the set of all pairs

hB, W i

occurring on it is.

Our aim in this section is to prove the following

U be a structure, let V be a nite set A be an L-formula such that hA, V i is R-satisable in U . Then every tableau starting with hA, V i has at least one branch that is simultaneously R-satisable in U . Lemma 3 (Soundness Lemma) Let

of free variables, and let

A is a senh¬A, ∅i is not R-

The soundness theorem follows readily from the lemma: If

h¬A, ∅i structures U .

tence and some tableau begun with satisable, hence

U A

for all

closes, then

The proof of the soundness lemma proceeds by way of induction along the generation of tableaux.

Since

the induction basis is trivial.

hA, V i

is R-satisable in

U

by assumption,

Applications of the propositional rules and

352

Kai F. Wehmeier

the negated quantier rules are easily handled by means of the induction hypothesis. Let us thus focus on the quantier instantiation rules. First, the universal case.

Suppose given a simultaneously R-satisable

T ∗ arise from T by extending B to B ∗ according to the universal instantiation rule. That is, there is a pair h∀xF [x], V i on B , and B ∗ results from B by writing the pair hF [a], V ∪ {a}i below its last node. Here, a does not occur in F , a 6∈ V , and one of the

branch

B

in a tableau

T,

and let

following two cases obtains:

hB, W i on B , a ∈ W . In this case, assuming that U -assignment that simultaneously R-satises B , ν will also ∗ simultaneously R-satisfy B : Since h∀xF [x], V i occurs on B , we know ν that U hF [u] , ν[V ]∪{u}i for every u ∈ U \ν[V ]; But because a 6∈ V , we know that ν(a) is such a u. Also, because ν is 1-1 on the union of all free-variable sets occurring on B , and no additional free variables ∗ occur on B , the requisite injectivity condition is still fullled.

1. For some pair

ν

is the

B are empty. In this case, too, ν B ∗ . We already know that it satises ν every pair on B . But since h∀xF [x], ∅i is on B , U hF [u] , {u}i for every u ∈ U , in particular, for ν(a). The injectivity condition is trivial.

2. All free-variable sets occurring on itself simultaneously R-satises

B , simultaneously R-satised ν , contains the entry h∃xF [x], V i and has been extended into k + 1 branches B1 , . . . , Bk+1 according to the existential instantiation rule. We know the fresh free variable a occurring for the rst time in the last entry on Bk+1 , i.e., in hF [a], V ∪ {a}i, is not an element of V . We also know that since ν R-satises h∃xF [x], V i, there is an element u ∈ U \ ν[V ] ν such that U hF [u] , ν[V ] ∪ {u}i. Fix such an element u. We distinguish Second, the existential case. Say the branch

by the assignment

two cases:

bi that occurs in one of the free-variable sets V , ν(bi ) = u. I claim that ν then simultaneously R-satises Bi : Clearly ν R-satises hF [bi ], V ∪ {bi }i in U ; It simultaneously R-satises B by induction hypothesis, and the injectivity

1. For some free variable on

B,

but not in

condition also follows from the induction hypothesis, as no new variables occur on

νua

Bi .

Bk+1 in U : It hF [a], V ∪{a}i, and it equally clearly simultaneously a R-satises B , because a is new to B . Further, νu is 1-1 on the union of all free-variable sets on B and {a} because a is new to B and u is not the ν -image of any free variable occurring in any of the free-variable sets on B .

2. Otherwise,

simultaneously R-satises the new branch

clearly R-satises

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53

353

7 Completeness The completeness proof follows the usual strategy of constructing a model

U

for an open branch

B

in a `systematic' tableau, where the domain of

the set of free variables occurring on

B.

U

is

In analogy with the Hintikka sets

of Smullyan (1968), we dene Ramsey sets, or R-sets for short, as follows.

hA, V i, where A is an L-formula and V a nite U be a non-empty set of free variables such that S {FV(A) ∪ V : hA, V i ∈ S} ⊆ U . Then S is an R-set for U if, whenever Let

S

be a set of pairs

set of free variables. Let

1.

hA, V i, hB, W i ∈ S

2.

h¬¬A, V i ∈ S ,

3.

hA ∧ B, V i ∈ S ,

4.

h¬(A ∧ B), V i ∈ S ,

and

then

A

B

is atomic, then

is not

¬A;

hA, V i ∈ S ;

then

hA, V i, hB, V i ∈ S ;

then

h¬A, V i ∈ S

or

h¬B, V i ∈ S ;

and similarly

for the other Boolean connectives; 5.

h∀xF [x], V i ∈ S ,

6.

h¬∀xF [x], V i ∈ S ,

7.

h∃xF [x], V i ∈ S ,

8.

h¬∃xF [x], V i ∈ S ,

then for every then

h∃x¬F [x], V i ∈ S ;

then for some then

b ∈ U \ V , hF [b], V ∪ {b}i ∈ S ;

b ∈ U \ V , hF [b], V ∪ {b}i ∈ S ;

h∀x¬F [x], V i ∈ S .

Lemma 4 (Hintikka's Lemma for R-logic) If

S

is simultaneously R-satisable in some structure

S is an R-set for U , then U with domain U .

S be an R-set for U . We turn U into a structure U by n-ary relation symbol P , the relation PU as follows: ha1 , . . . , an i ∈ PU :⇔ for some V, hP a1 . . . an , V i ∈ S . Let ν be the U -assignment that maps every variable a in U to itself, and maps every other variable to an arbitrarily selected element of U . Note that, since ν is the identity function on all relevant free variables, in what follows ν we needn't distinguish between L-formulas A and L(U)-sentences A , nor between nite sets V of free variables and their images ν[V ] under ν . Toward a proof, let

dening, for any given

We claim that (a) whenever

hA, V i ∈ S ,

(b) whenever

h¬A, V i ∈ S ,

then

U hA, V i,

then

and

U 6 hA, V i.

354

Kai F. Wehmeier

L-formula A.

A, U hP a1 . . . an , V i. Then, by denition of U , for some W , hP a1 . . . an , W i ∈ S . Since S is an R-set, it follows that h¬P a1 . . . an , V i 6∈ S . If A is of the form ¬B , then part (a) follows from the induction hypothesis, part (b). For part (b), if h¬¬B, V i ∈ S , then since S is an R-set, also hB, V i ∈ S , and so by the induction hypothesis, part (a), U hB, V i, i.e., U 6 h¬B, V i. The other Boolean connectives can be handled analogously, The proof proceeds by induction on the

U.

part (a) follows from the denition of

For atomic

For part (b), suppose

using the requisite induction hypotheses.

A is ∀xF [x]. For part (a), assume h∀xF [x], V i ∈ S . Since S U , we know that for all b ∈ U \V , hF [b], V ∪{b}i ∈ S . Thus by part (a) of the induction hypothesis, for all b ∈ U \ V , U hF [b], V ∪ {b}i, i.e., U h∀xF [x], V i. For part (b), suppose h¬∀xF [x], V i ∈ S . Since S is an R-set for U , h∃x¬F [x], V i ∈ S , and thus for some b ∈ U \ V , h¬F [b], V ∪ {b}i ∈ S . Part (b) of the induction hypothesis then implies that for some b ∈ U \ V , U 6 hF [b], V ∪ {b}i; hence U 6 h∀xF [x], V i. The Now suppose

is an R-set for

existential case is entirely analogous. Q.e.d. Next we describe a systematic procedure for generating tableaux.

For

the purpose, we will assume that the free variables come ordered in an

ω -sequence. To systematically generate tableaux, iterate the following steps as long as possible. 1. Pick, if possible, the highest and leftmost pair checkmark next to it and such that

A

hA, V i

that has no

is non-atomic.

2. If the previous step is inapplicable, pick the highest and leftmost pair

hA, V i, with A of the form ∀xF [x], that has the least number of checkmarks, and to which universal instantiation can be applied with respect to at least one branch passing through it. 3. If both previous steps are inapplicable, the systematic procedure terminates. 4. Apply the applicable rule to the chosen pair form

∀xF [x],

hA, V i.

If

A

is of the

pick the instantiating free variable so that it is the rst

eligible free variable

a

such that the resulting instance

yet occur on the branch at hand. branch, pick the rst free variable. 5. Put a check mark next to the pair

F [a]

does not

If no free variables occur on the

hA, V i.

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53

355

We now dene a systematic tableau to be either 1. the result of the systematic procedure, if it terminates after nitely many iterations, or 2. if the systematic procedure does not terminate after any nite number of iterations, the limit (set-theoretic union) of the results of all nite stages of the systematic procedure.

Lemma 5 Every non-closed branch

for

UB :=

S

{W : for

some

B

L-formula

of a systematic tableau is an R-set

B,

hB, W i

occurs on

B}.6

For a proof, note that condition (1) on R-sets is satised because

B

is an

open branch. The other conditions, with the possible exception of (5), are obviously satised by construction. Now consider condition (5). Suppose that

b

h∀xF [x], V i occurs on B and that b ∈ UB \ V . The free variable UB through some application of either universal or existential

entered

instantiation. The systematic procedure ensures that, at some point after the rst occurrence of

h∀xF [x], V i

b

on

B,

universal instantiation will be applied to

with respect to the free variable

also occur on

B,

b.

Hence

hF [b], V ∪ {b}i

will

which concludes the proof of the lemma.

The completeness theorem now follows as usual:

Theorem 1 If a sentence

A

is R-valid, then there exists a proof of

a closed tableau beginning with

For if there are no closed tableaux for tableaux for

A.

A

(i.e.,

h¬A, ∅i). A, then there are no closed systematic A is nite, it follows immedi-

If the systematic tableau for

ately that it must contain a non-closed branch. If the systematic tableau for

A

is innite, then by König's lemma, it contains an innite branch, which

is clearly non-closed. In either case, by the previous lemma, the systematic tableau for

A

contains a branch

B

that is an R-set for

lemma for R-logic, there is thus a structure R-true. Hence

h¬A, ∅i

is satisable, and

A

U

UB .

By Hintikka's

in which all pairs on

B

are

is not R-valid.

6 Note that U cannot be empty: Let the initial node be hA, FV(A)i. If A isn't an B L-sentence, FV(A) and hence UB isn't empty. Otherwise, since L contains no individual constants, A must contain a quantier. Thus, after nitely many steps, the systematic

procedure will attempt to apply either universal or existential instantiation in each open branch. Now suppose all free-variable sets were empty. In that case, (i) existential instantiation does not result in branching and introduces a fresh free variable into the branch, and (ii) universal instantiation is applicable (condition (b) of the rule being fullled) and similarly introduces a fresh free variable into the branch.

356

Kai F. Wehmeier

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Boolos, G. (1984). Trees and Finite Satisability: Proof of a Conjecture of Burgess, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 25, no. 3, pp.193-197. Hintikka, J. (1956). Identity, Variables, and Impredicative Denitions, Symbolic Logic, vol. 21, pp.225-245. Schütte, K. (1977).

Proof Theory,

Smullyan, R.M. (1968).

Journal of

Springer-Verlag, New York.

First-Order Logic,

Springer-Verlag, New York.

Wehmeier, K.F. (2004). Wittgensteinian Predicate Logic, vol. 45, no. 1, pp.1-11.

Formal Logic,

Notre Dame Journal of

Wehmeier, K.F. (2008). Wittgensteinian Tableaux, Identity, and Co-Denotation, Erkenntnis, vol. 69, no. 3, pp.363-376. Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Wittgenstein, L. (1995).

Logico-Philosophicus,

transl. C. K. Ogden,

Cambridge Letters: correspondence with Russell, Keynes, Moore, Ramsey, and Sraa, ed. B. McGuinness and G. H. von Wright, Blackwell,

Oxford.

On Ramsey's `Silly Delusion' regarding Tractatus 5.53

F. This would be true in a two-element domain in which both elements satisfy the ...... 〈A, V 〉, with A of the form ∀xF[x], that has the least number of check- marks ...

405KB Sizes 1 Downloads 191 Views

Recommend Documents

Clarification on exemption regarding change.PDF
There was a problem loading more pages. Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. Clarification on exemption regarding change.PDF. Clarificati

Clarification on exemption regarding change.PDF
examination was held-in two parts. ... Clarilication on exemption regarding change in pattern of Appendix 3(IREM) ... As such, with restoration of earlier pattern.

Tractatus logico-philosophicus
diferentes valores fx constituyen un grupo de proposiciones. Podemos extender la idea «no-p y no-q» tanto como aplicarla a la negación simultánea de todas ...

Silly Telugu Jokes.pdf
... Association is an anti-corruption body. B- Transparency International publishes an annual report about the level. of corruption in most countries of the world. C- So you think there are chances of winning the fight against corruption. D- Sorry to

Silly Telugu Jokes.pdf
Sign in. Page. 1. /. 50. Loading… Page 1 of 50. Page 1 of 50. Page 2 of 50. Page 2 of 50. Page 3 of 50. Page 3 of 50. Page 4 of 50. Page 4 of 50. Silly Telugu ...

JanuaryChilly Silly Snowmen.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. JanuaryChilly Silly Snowmen.pdf. JanuaryChilly Silly Snowmen.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main me

07-03-2018 Regarding Recommendation of Committee on Medical ...
Mar 7, 2018 - There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. 07-03-2018 Regarding Recommendation of Committee o ... emester Regular & Back Examination 2017

Letter S: Seal's Silly Sandwich
Feb 1, 2001 - Irresistible Animal Storybooks That Build Phonemic Awareness & Teach ... This is why we advise you to constantly see this web page when you ...

Circle Minecraft Generator Codes 553
Private Bukkit Plugin Developer. ... Code Generator Hack Minecraft Account 2017 Live Free Game Generator ... Codes on Apple TV, Free Game Generator Codes Seed Generator Minecraft Ps4 Code Generator Particle Generator Minecraft.

Further reflections on questions regarding Genetics ... -
recent research paper, Are cognitive g and academic achievement g one and ... Professors Robert Plomin and Ian Deary, two top experts on genetics and IQ, .... 20th century (Clarence Darrow, Bertrand Russell, H.L. Mencken, Robert Ingersoll, ...

wittgenstein - tractatus logico philosophicus [portugues].pdf ...
president, during a Camp David trip. Reagan said yesterday that. although he was acquainted with. Palmer, he could not recall whether. the dean had spoken of the Whar- ton/Contra connection during discus- sions about Iran. "I really don't remember if

wittgenstein - tractatus logico philosophicus [portugues].pdf ...
Page 3 of 82. wittgenstein - tractatus logico philosophicus [portugues].pdf. wittgenstein - tractatus logico philosophicus [portugues].pdf. Open. Extract. Open with.

the god delusion dawkins.pdf
Retrying... the god delusion dawkins.pdf. the god delusion dawkins.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying the god delusion dawkins.pdf.

Mermaid Tail Fin Pattern - The Silly Pearl.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. Mermaid Tail Fin ...

Silly Sentences Roll An Adjective.pdf
Silly Sentences Roll An Adjective.pdf. Silly Sentences Roll An Adjective.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying Silly Sentences Roll An ...

Pro Evolution Soccer 2017 Crack Download 553
Apr 6, 2017 - Pro Evolution Soccer 2013 ( PES 2013) oyunu serial CD key. ... Code Generator Pes 17 Crack Android Application Live Free Game Generator ...

Clarification regarding clarification.PDF
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. Clarification ...Missing:

DW_Notice regarding parking_football game_fall festival_eng_span ...
Otoño a la semana siguiente, pero si el éxito de Brewster continúa, habrá otro partido la próxima. semana. Por lo tanto, será el anfitrión de tres eventos en la ...

FLVS Dave Ramseys Foundations in Personal Finance Spring ...
FLVS Dave Ramseys Foundations in Personal Finance Spring Supplement 6.pdf. FLVS Dave Ramseys Foundations in Personal Finance Spring Supplement 6.