ARTICLE IN PRESS Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) 00, 1–11 doi:10.1098/rstb.2011.0177

1 2

65 66

3

67

4

68

Research

5

69 70

6 7 8 9 10 11

Positive feedback and alternative stable states in inbreeding, cooperation, sex roles and other evolutionary processes

14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32

Jussi Lehtonen and Hanna Kokko* Division of Ecology, Evolution and Genetics, Research School of Biology, Australian National University, Canberra, Australian Capital Territory 0200, Australia Much of systems science studies regulatory processes involving a mixture of positive and negative feedbacks. Evolutionary ecology textbooks are full of examples that feature negative feedback, e.g. in the form of density dependence (population regulation) or frequency-dependent selection (polymorphisms). Positive feedback in this field is likewise common, but in stark contrast with negative feedback; examples are often studied in isolation from each other. Evolutionary examples include Fisherian ‘runaway’ sexual selection, the evolution of cooperation, selfing and inbreeding tolerance under purging of deleterious alleles, and the evolution of sex differences in parental care. All these examples feature self-reinforcing processes where the increase in the value of a trait selects for further increases, sometimes via a coevolutionary feedback loop with another trait. Positive feedback often leads to alternative stable states (evolutionary endpoints), making the interpretation of evolutionary predictions challenging. We discuss here conceptual issues such as the relationship between selfreinforcing selection and disruptive selection, and develop one example in detail: the relationship between the operational sex ratio and sexual selection, and its influence on the evolution of biparental or uniparental care. Keywords: frequency dependence; feedback; alternative stable states

35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60

1. INTRODUCTION Negative feedback is a common theme in evolutionary ecology as a stabilizing factor. Positive feedback, in contrast, describes self-reinforcing, de-stabilizing processes; by favouring a type that is already common, it often leads to alternative stable states. Much of systems science can be characterized as the study of regulatory processes involving a mixture of positive and negative feedbacks [1– 3]. In ecology, alternative stable states ([4], review) often differ greatly in their practical consequences. Examples include near irreversible collapses of fish stocks from their original states of abundance [5,6], or disease outbreaks as a result of compromised herd immunity when too small a proportion of individuals is vaccinated [7]. Inverse density dependence—a form of positive feedback (better per capita growth in larger than small populations)—can drive a population extinct via an Allee effect. Here, a population that has experienced a stochastic reduction in its size may now be within the basin of attraction of extinction (these basins outline which of the alternative equilibria are reached from given starting conditions). Allee effects can be created in many ways [8], including a positive feedback where overexploitation of rare species becomes self-reinforcing because humans attribute value to rarity [9].

Studies of alternative stable states in evolutionary biology (our focus here) are scarcer than in ecology, despite many examples featuring positive feedback [10]. We describe connections between alternative stable states and disruptive selection, followed by examples of alternative stable states in evolutionary processes, with new theory on parental sex roles. Finally, we will comment on the challenges of testing evolutionary predictions that feature alternative equilibria.

74 75 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96

62

*Author for correspondence ([email protected]).

63

One contribution of 16 to a Discussion Meeting Issue ‘Predictive ecology: systems approaches’.

1 rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108

2. IS DISRUPTIVE SELECTION SYNONYMOUS WITH POSITIVE FEEDBACK? NO Disruptive selection occurs when intermediate phenotypes have a fitness disadvantage compared with more extreme phenotypes. At first sight, it seems logical that disruptive selection would easily lead to alternative stable states at both extremes. This is, however, only partly true. Disruptive selection can be divided into two categories, one of which can indeed lead to alternative stable states, whereas the other results in protected polymorphisms [11]. The type of disruptive selection that does not lead to alternative stable states occurs when disruptive selection is associated with negative feedback. Consider a population exploiting a resource of varying sizes (such as small and large seeds). Consumption affects the availability of the resource (figure 1a; note that size variation can also be continuous [12]). If individuals that are best at exploiting a certain seed size become relatively more abundant, then this part of

61

64

73

97

33 34

72

76

12 13

71

This journal is q 2011 The Royal Society

109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128

ARTICLE IN PRESS 2 129

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

Positive feedback in evolution 193

(a)

130

194

131

195

132

196

133

197 198

134 135 136 137

(b)

138 139

x-axis = resource size = resource abundance = distribution of specialization on resource sizes

199 200 201 202 203

140

204

141

205

142

206

143

207 208

144 145 146 147 148

Figure 1. Why disruptive selection is not synonymous with positive feedback. (a) Disruptive selection leads to a protected polymorphisms, and because all deviations from the initial state lead to the same state, there are no alternative stable states (even though the one state comprises two alternative strategies). (b) Initial deviations become reinforced, and this leads to two alternative stable states.

153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178

the resource size range becomes depleted. Phenotypes that deviate from the majority now have an advantage. Instead of multiple equilibria, this can maintain a stable, protected polymorphism in the population. Even though two trait values (alternative strategies) coexist, the polymorphism itself is not an example of a set of alternative stable states. Instead, the population has reached one stable state, which is a polymorphism with two coexisting trait values. Of more interest are scenarios where disruptive selection (suboptimal fitness of an intermediate phenotype) combines with positive feedback (suboptimal fitness of a rare phenotype). Consider a consumer that feeds on two fruit (with large and small seeds for example) and the plant relies on frugivory for germination (figure 1b). As before, intermediate phenotypes are not able to efficiently use either resource, which initially creates similar bimodal distributions as mentioned already, but now selection can make a population specialize on one of the two seed sizes. If the majority specializes on, say small seeds, then the plant with small seeds is germinated more efficiently and increases in abundance. The payoff for specializing on small seeds then increases in a self-reinforcing way. In this case, there are truly two alternative stable states in the population. From this hypothetical example, we will now move on to consider real-life examples of positive feedback and self-reinforcing selection.

179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192

211 212 214

150 152

210

213

149 151

209

3. POSITIVE FEEDBACK ON A SINGLE TRAIT (a) Inbreeding tolerance Inbred offspring can inherit an identical copy of a deleterious recessive allele from both parents, which can markedly reduce offspring viability or other fitness components [13]. On the other hand, inbreeding has kin-selected benefits [14 – 17]: a sib-mating mother has 50 per cent genetic advantage because the offspring has a 50 per cent chance of harbouring not one but two gene copies that are identical by descent to those of the mother. The kin-selected benefit of inbreeding and the cost of inbreeding depression do Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

not necessarily cancel out. Their balance determines whether inbreeding is adaptive [15]. Lande & Schemske [18] made it explicit that the process involves positive feedback. In plants, if only few individuals reproduce by selfing (an extreme form of inbreeding), then they will do so in a population harbouring many recessive deleterious alleles. Inbreeding depression is consequently strong, and selfing is selected against. Inbreeding depression will be much weaker, however, if the population is already inbred because harmful recessives will have been purged from the population [19]. The more there is inbreeding, the easier it is for the benefits to override the costs. This self-reinforcing nature of selection for inbreeding made Lande & Schemske [18] predict that plants should mostly reproduce by selfing, or mostly outbreed; intermediates should be unstable. Lande & Schemske’s paper [18] is a good example of work that has led to fruitful research avenues, while making predictions that are at least partially wrong. Categorizing plant species according to the frequency of selfing reveals a u-shaped frequency distribution: very low and very high selfing frequencies predominate [20]. However, about one-third of plant species have an intermediate selfing rate [20,21], which is hard to explain if positive feedback is the only factor at play. A multitude of possible explanations for such mixed mating strategies have been proposed since [22]. Without the groundbreaking work that produced the prediction that only the two ends of the distribution would be stable, the relevance of the question ‘why does mixed mating occur?’ might have remained undiscovered for quite a while. Unsurprisingly for research focused on plants, Lande & Schemske’s paper [18] has received far less attention in the animal than in the plant literature. Approximately, 70 per cent of the 817 citing studies refer to plants, 20 per cent to animals and 10 per cent are modelling studies. Animal studies state commonly enough that inbreeding can prevail when inbreeding depression is mild, but the self-reinforcing nature of the process is rarely commented on (e.g. [17,23,24], but see also [25,26]).

215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256

ARTICLE IN PRESS Positive feedback in evolution 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306

(b) Cooperate but only if others do too. . . Arguments regarding the evolution of cooperation often distinguish between the origin and maintenance of prosocial tendencies. For example, it is difficult to see why eusociality should evolve if colony-level relatedness is low, but the first eusocial insects may have avoided this problem if their queens mated monogamously— opening the door for eusociality even if queens later evolve multiple mating. This pattern is indeed found in phylogenetic studies [27], including contexts that are not strictly eusocial (cooperative breeding in birds [28]). Some animal societies have been argued to have reached ‘points of no return’ [29] or ‘dead-ends’ [30]. This occurs when an individual never develops outside a colony with highly differentiated division of labour. A complex suite of traits can then evolve; from that point, it can be difficult to evolve back to simpler Q1 lifestyles with independent breeding. More general models of cooperation, built without a specific taxon in mind, likewise often predict alternative equilibria that differ greatly in cooperativeness. One of the classic models is the iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma, where ‘tit for tat’, which starts out behaving cooperatively and then copies its partner’s moves, forms a stable equilibrium—but so does ‘always defect’, which cannot be invaded by ‘tit for tat’ [31]. The finding that ‘cooperation can be difficult to get started, but becomes more robust once established’, repeats itself in many other models (e.g. the evolution of policing [32]). Tit-for-tat games feature immediate reciprocity. Reciprocity can also occur in a broader sense: cooperative systems often feature young helpers, some of which later proceed to a dominant status and now become receivers of help. Such systems can be stable against freeriders [33], but the establishment phase is difficult: why begin helping if it is never reciprocated? This can give rise to two equilibria, with and without help [33,34]. The no-help equilibrium can become unstable and disappear, however, if there is some reason to contribute to the common good that does not depend on receiving help. Safety in numbers (in the form of predator dilution) is the simplest way to achieve such a kick-start [33,35]. Kinship is possibly the commonest, but mutualistic relationships can also evolve between unrelated species. For example, Wolbachia (an endosymbiont parasite of insects) has also been observed to reach the alternative state of an obligate mutualist in at least two independent evolutionary transitions; such an evolutionary transition again offers no easy way back to independent living [36].

307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320

4. COEVOLVING MULTIPLE TRAITS: A PLETHORA OF (MOSTLY SEXUAL) EXAMPLES Reviewing alternative stable states in a coevolutionary context offers us a wealth of examples. The coevolving traits could belong to different species, and mutualism is not the only example; coevolution of predators and their prey are a well-studied example [37]. Alternatively, the traits can be characteristics of the same organism. Schaffer & Rosenzweig [38] present an early example where an organism can, depending on its ancestral state, evolve two or more different life histories based on the same trade-offs. The relevant set of coevolving traits Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

3

is reproductive expenditure (RE) at each age. For example, RE in the first year affects the optimum RE in the second year, and vice versa, leading to coevolution where alternative stable combinations can be reached depending on the initial values: the same set of tradeoffs can lead to iteroparity or semelparity (reproduction over several years or just once as a form of terminal effort). Perhaps because of the distinctness of male and female traits, sexual interactions form the arguably best-studied examples of positive feedback, and we thus draw most of our examples from this field.

321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332

(a) Males and females. . . or just two types of gametes? The evolution of maleness and femaleness provides an interesting case study of alternative stable states. Males and females do not exist in all sexually reproducing species. One speaks of ‘mating types’ if gametes of equal size fuse to form a zygote (isogamy), and the terminology of ‘males’ is only used if one gamete type evolves to be much smaller than the other (anisogamy). Disruptive selection can make sexes specialize in producing numerous, small ‘searcher’ gametes (sperm) or fewer and larger ‘resource provider’ gametes (eggs) [39,40]. Self-reinforcing selection towards small ‘searcher’ gametes may require a threshold asymmetry in gamete size. Below this threshold, gamete sizes evolve back towards equality, especially once internal fertilization evolves; above, one gamete type evolves to be much smaller than the other [41,42]. Recent modelling recognizes the importance of alternative stable states in gamete evolution [42]. The equilibrium with isogamy (equally sized gametes) can cease to be stable even in the absence of gamete competition, if gametes have trouble finding each other through low gamete production or encounter rates, or through high gamete mortality. But isogamy also breaks down if the more numerous gametes compete intensely for the less numerous ones, i.e. if there are gametes from several adults in the same locality. Anisogamy by itself comprises two alternative stable states, because it is not predefined which mating type evolves to specialize in the production of small gametes. If there are two mating types (x and y), then the two alternative stable states are (x ¼ male, y ¼ female) and (x ¼ female, y ¼ male), despite the end results looking similar owing to symmetry. If the conditions for the evolution of anisogamy are present, then theory predicts that the type with the initially smaller gametes will be able to keep decreasing its gamete size (in evolutionary time, owing to gamete competition or possibly gamete limitation) until a minimum size is reached. The other type is simultaneously ‘forced’ to increase its gamete size in order to maintain reasonable zygote survival, which also increases zygote survival for the other mating type despite its smaller gamete size. Later, a researcher will simply choose to label the individuals with small gametes as ‘males’ because males by definition produce the small gametes. Isogamy can be a third alternative stable state [42].

333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381

(b) Sexual selection and mate choice Once anisogamy has evolved, creating two sexes, their roles in reproduction give rise to many types of positive

382 383 384

ARTICLE IN PRESS 4 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

Positive feedback in evolution

feedback. A sexual signal (often produced by a male) and a preference for this signal in the opposite sex form a good example. Positive feedback between these two traits has been hypothesized since the 1930s: this forms the basis of the Fisher [43] process where a trait and a preference become genetically linked and may self-reinforce each other towards greater exaggeration of the trait and the preference alike (‘runaway’ evolution [44]). Because any trait might become preferred in this way, evolving in arbitrary directions, the model has been used to make the prediction that related species should enter numerous alternative stable states and exhibit great across-species variation in their secondary sexual characteristics [45] (but see [46,47] for a critique of too simplistic models of speciation via sexual selection). Fisherian sexual selection was initially modelled in an open-ended fashion, with no boundaries on how far a preference or a trait could go. Depending on parameter values, populations reach a neutral line along which drift occurs or experience an open-ended ‘runaway’ with its endpoint not explicitly modelled ([48]; for later models, see [44]). The process still forms the cornerstone of sexual selection for genetic (indirect) benefits [49], although it appears fragile when modified to include likely real-life phenomena, such as costs of female preference expression (even minute costs destroy the runaway, unless there is recurrent mutation [50]). A more general view of the Fisherian process avoids restricting attention to purely arbitrary traits, which require zero correlation between the trait and any other characteristic of the male. Instead, the ‘Fisher–Zahavi process’ assumes covariation with other heritable traits of the male that influence offspring reproductive value. Solutions then include stable equilibria where female preference expression can be costly, and the male trait does not exaggerate further nor does it disappear despite natural selection against the present level of exaggeration [51–53]. Again, these models feature multiple equilibria. It makes no sense for a female to evolve a costly preference if the male trait is not present and thus cannot reveal differences among males. But if females do not prefer any male over another, a male who displays a costly trait will not have its display traits selected for—a classic chicken-and-egg problem. The equilibrium of no trait, and no preference for it, is stable (e.g. figure 2 in Kokko et al. [53]) and surrounded by a basin of attraction where individuals expressing preferences or displays are selected against (much like the problem of the origin of cooperation mentioned earlier). In other words, the trivial equilibrium (no preference, no trait) and the more interesting equilibrium (sexual trait and a preference for it) are separated by a fitness valley. The population should somehow be displaced to jump over the valley such that the self-reinforcing process towards interesting outcomes gets its necessary kick-start [53]. A potential solution is that the nontrivial equilibrium usually predicts very asymmetric costs of male and female traits. Because indirect benefits are usually not large in magnitude [55], females are never expected to evolve very costly preferences for them. Relatively cost-free levels of preferences can nevertheless put a strong selective pressure on the male trait. For Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

example, females who turn up at a lek at the most convenient time with respect to the females’ own breeding schedules, and mate with a random male present at the time, will select for males with above-average display stamina [56]. This can make crossing fitness valleys easier: females are not heavily penalized for expressing preferences that initially yield no benefit, whereas males are strongly selected to respond to such preferences. Genetic drift on female traits, or various sensory biases that predispose females to be attracted to certain male characteristics, can help evolution cross such fitness valleys towards more interesting equilibria [53,57], but empirical tests of such ideas are largely lacking [58]—as are explicit theoretical studies of drift in this context.

449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465

(c) Same trait, different sexes? The evolution of mate searching and parental care In our earlier-mentioned examples, the two sexes expressed very different traits. Preferences or ornaments can also be more symmetrically expressed by the sexes (for mutual mate choice, see [59,60]). There is arguably an even more interesting set of traits where it is not obvious whether males or females, or both, should develop them. Mating systems feature several tasks that should be performed by one of the two sexes or both, and good performance by one sex reduces selection for the other to put as much effort in the task. If males search for females, females do not need to [61]; if females take good care of offspring, males do not need to [62]. Mate searching and parental care are the most obvious traits that can, in principle at least, be ‘interchangeably’ performed by either parent—or jointly. Inbreeding avoidance (see above) belongs to the same category, if it is achieved through dispersal [63,64]. Why then is there often a sex difference in these traits? Adult individuals of either sex can engage in matefinding activities. It is not immediately obvious why the sex that produces sperm should also perform the majority of any mate-searching tasks. Models that lack sperm competition indeed predict two alternative stable states: either the female or the male can evolve to become the searcher [61,65] or—if search costs accelerate rapidly with search effort—both may evolve to move equally much in search of each other ([65]; this solution features no alternative stable states but a single joint solution for both sexes). Including sperm competition appears to make males the predominant searcher [65], but this conclusion appears robust only if females do not benefit as much from multiple mating as males. If females benefit greatly from multiple mating, e.g. via increased fecundity when consuming multiple nuptial gifts, then this can flip the system to an equilibrium where females are the predominant searchers (J. McCartney et al. unpublished manuscript). Q2

466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507

(i) Uniparental or biparental care? A grand battle between positive and negative feedback Early models on parental care [66 – 68] showed how the fitness of each sex depends on the behaviour of the other, but the payoffs themselves remained rather

508 509 510 511 512

ARTICLE IN PRESS Positive feedback in evolution (b)

513

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

5 577

5

578

514 515

1

516

579

0

2

580

517

581

518

582

519

583

520

584

521

585

522

586

523

587

524

(d) 0.4

526 527 528 529 530 531

male care duration

525

0.3

(a)

5 1

0

(e)

5 1

2

0

2

588

5 1

589 590

0

2

592

0.2

593 594 595

0.1

596

532 533 534

591

597

0

535

598 599

(c)

536

5

600 601

537

1

538

0

2

602

539

603

540

604

541

605

542

606

543

607 608

544

0

545 546

0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 female care duration

549 550 551 552 553 554 555

Figure 2. Evolutionary trajectories of coevolving parental care duration of females (x-axis) and males (y-axis), with stable alternative states indicated as dots. Small grey boxes depict the shape of the relationship between sexual selection (y-axis: ~ ranging between 1 and 5) and the OSR (x-axis ranging between 0 and 2); for females, the relationship is mirrored (not k ~ O Þ ¼ 1 þ 4ð1 þ eðaðrO bÞÞ Þ1 , with (a) a ¼ 50, shown; see text). This relationship is of a logistic shape in all examples, kðr b ¼ 1.2, (b) a ¼ 5, b ¼ 1.2, (c) a ¼ 1, b ¼ 1.2, (d) a ¼ 50, b ¼ 1.05 and (e) a ¼ 50, b ¼ 1.3. Panels are arranged such that ~ curve, horizontal deviations shift it horizontally without changing the slope. vertical deviations shift the slope of the OSR-k ~ ¼ 1) and all mortalities per time unit are There is no multiple mating (in the notation of Kokko & Jennions [54]; n ¼ n equal to 0.01.

558 559 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576

612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620

556 557

610 611

547 548

609

arbitrarily defined. The payoff (or probability of remating) of a deserting parent was assumed constant. Later, it was understood that the payoffs should evolve as the frequency of parenting and deserting types in the population changes. A deserter cannot gain much reproductive success if individuals of the opposite sex are busy caring for young and hence not available for matings. This negative feedback on desertion stabilizes mixed strategies where only some individuals of a given sex desert their young [69]. The importance of negative feedback has since become prominent in sex role theory: it has overturned older arguments for the prevalence of female (as opposed to male) care (see [54,70] commenting on Trivers [66]). The essence of the argument is that it is incorrect to claim that the sex producing small gametes suffers a relatively smaller loss of fitness if offspring die because of insufficient care. Males can only reproduce if they find females to reproduce with (Fisher condition Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

sensu [71]). If most females are busy caring, then a male cannot achieve much fitness searching for (nonexistent) females ready to mate. The more there are Q3 males competing to find new mates, the more profitable does caring for young become as an alternative route to male fitness (reviewed in earlier studies [54,72]). This makes it hard to argue that there should be self-reinforcing selection that makes sex roles diverge; such selection requires positive rather than negative frequency dependence. New models of parental sex roles [54,70,72] offer several explanations for why one sex nevertheless can end up with the lion’s share of parenting duties. If there is multiple mating per brood, then males will typically have less parentage in a brood than females, and this selects against male care. Caring is also selected for in the sex that is more common in the adult sex ratio. Finally, if there is sexual selection, then this makes the sexually selected sex a less likely carer. Why? Sexual selection implies that mating

621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640

ARTICLE IN PRESS 6 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

Positive feedback in evolution

success is not random. The stronger sexual selection is, the more confident mated individuals of the sexually selected sex can be of their mating success after Q4 desertion. These individuals possess traits that make their mating success a repeatable feat. This can tip the ‘care or desert?’ balance in favour of deserting if sexual selection is strong [72]. The situation as a whole combines negative feedback with the possibility of positive feedback. An overabundance of one sex in the mating pool (technically expressed as a bias in the ‘operational sex ratio’, OSR) has two effects that oppose each other. Both stem from the same fact that the sex that currently cares little is likely to be abundant in the OSR and will have trouble securing new matings. As stated earlier, negative frequency dependence (Fisher condition) selects for more care in the sex that currently cares little: ‘if it is difficult to find a new mate, make the most of the current breeding attempt’. But mating difficulties can also set the stage for sexual selection where a subset of individuals perform much better than others in a competitive situation. This creates the potential for positive frequency dependence where the less-caring sex is self-reinforcingly selected to care ever less. The following thought process (which we here exemplify using a male perspective) gives the details of the positive feedback. Assume some initial asymmetry, e.g. males initially provide a little less care than females, say, for reasons of uncertain parentage. They thus spend more time than females in the mating pool: they are abundant in the OSR. This creates mating difficulties for males. If males also experience stronger sexual selection than females, mating success of mated males becomes repeatable, which selects for a further reduction in male care. Thus, the numbers of males keep building up in the mating pool, which again aggravate male mating difficulties. The Achilles heel of this argument (and the reason why an explicit model is needed) can be found in the ‘if ’ in the above paragraph. It may sound plausible that traits that improve mating success only become relevant when matings are hard to achieve, i.e. when the OSR is biased towards the focal sex—to the extent that some authors have recommended OSR as a measure of sexual selection itself ([73]; for data on widespread usage to date see [74]). However, one should not conflate difficulties of obtaining matings (captured by the OSR) with the statement that mating success is repeatable (not captured by the OSR). The latter requires not only that matings are difficult to achieve but also that success is predicted by properties that vary across individuals [74]. Therefore, there is no specific fixed relationship between these factors, and the strength of sexual selection could even decrease with increasing OSR [75]. The relevant aspect of sexual selection for parental sex roles is the extent to which mating is a predictor of an individual’s future mating success [54]. This determines whether a mated individual (an individual in the position to desert or to care for its young) expects high enough mating success so that abandoning the current young is favoured. In Kokko & Jennions [54], sexual selection was measured as k (or ~ for males), the future success of any mated k Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

individual, if it returns to the mating pool, compared with the average success of individuals of this sex in the mating pool. Thus, if k ¼ 1, then there is no difference and mating is random. If individuals vary in, for example, body size, and mated individuals are larger than average, then individuals observed to mate once also enjoy above-average mating success in the future, expressed as k . 1. This value was fixed for each scenario investigated by Kokko & Jennions [54]. Earlier, we have stated the need to examine how sexual selection varies with the OSR. Although a precise, universal mathematical relationship relating OSR to k does not exist, we extend the basic model [54] by ~ functions of the OSR in a biologically making k and k plausible way (figure 2). When assuming a specific relationship between the OSR and sexual selection, we make both sexes obey the same relationship but, obviously, the relevant OSR for males is mirrored by 1/OSR for females. This is because the OSR is conventionally defined as rO ¼ number of males/females that are ready to mate at a given point in time. This is clearest in an example: if we assume that two males per ~ ¼ 1:5) female creates sexual selection on males (say k and very mild sexual selection on females (k ¼ 1.01), then by symmetry, the condition of two females per ~ ¼ 1:01 and male, all else being equal, should have k k ¼ 1.5. The former situation has rO ¼ 2; the latter has 1/rO ¼ 2. Females become sexually selected under conditions that exactly mirror those that make males sexually selected, while the model still allows us to investigate any relationship between k and the OSR (including cases where mating is always random, or alternatively, sexual selection operates on both sexes ~ O Þ . 1 and simultaneously, as all this requires is kðr k(1/rO) . 1). We are free to explore any function (symmetric or asymmetric) to relate OSR to sexual selection ~ O Þ ¼ kð1=rO Þ for all values of rO. as long as kðr We refer the reader to Kokko & Jennions [54] for the full model description. Here, we are interested in finding out whether an increase in sexual selection ~ experienced by one of the (parameters k and k) sexes, once the OSR has evolved to deviate from 1 : 1, can become self-reinforcing. If it can, the positive sexual selection feedback may override the negative feedback that arises via mating difficulties of the common sex in the OSR, and sex roles can diverge. An example of where this happens is found in figure 2a. If sexual selection targets the common sex in the OSR with increasing strength as the OSR becomes more biased (for the shape of the relationship see the grey box in figure 2a), then self-reinforcing sexual selection can indeed overcome the negative frequency dependence towards biparental solutions, but only if the ancestral state of the population is biased such that one sex already stays with the young for longer (evolutionary trajectories in figure 2a). We thus find a total of three equilibria: biparental care, and uniparental care by either the female or the male (figure 2a). While figure 2a shows that an ancestral biparental population with OSR ¼ 1 : 1 experiences no selection to move away from this equilibrium, this result is derived assuming that no significant sexual selection operates on ~ ¼ 1 at OSR ¼ either sex at OSR ¼ 1 : 1 (grey box: k ¼ k 1). But because biparental systems often feature mutual

705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730 731 732 733 734 735 736 737 738 739 740 741 742 743 744 745 746 747 748 749 750 751 752 753 754 755 756 757 758 759 760 761 762 763 764 765 766 767 768

ARTICLE IN PRESS Positive feedback in evolution mate choice [59,76], figure 2a alone gives a restricted view on the possibilities existing in nature. By altering ~  relationship; we can also conthe slope of the OSR-k sider scenarios where significant sexual selection is already present at OSR ¼ 1 : 1. We find that this can destroy biparental care, if deviations from OSR ¼ 1 : 1 immediately strengthen sexual selection on the sex towards which the OSR becomes biased (uniparental care in figure 2b). Alternatively, it can destroy the stability of the two uniparental equilibria, if the strength of sexual selection responds only mildly to variations around OSR ¼ 1 : 1 (biparental care in figure 2c). The intuitive reason for the difference is that the selfreinforcing process of sexual selection must kick in with strongly increasing force for the more abundant sex in the OSR, as its abundance creates negative feedback on care differences, which pulls solutions back towards biparental care. The positive feedback (strengthening sexual selection) is strong enough to overcome the negative feedback in figure 2b, while it remains too mild in figure 2c. These results complement earlier theoretical predictions that mutual mate choice can coexist with biparental care but only as long as sex differences in parental investment remain modest [16,76]. ~ relationship in The mild slopes for the OSR-k figures 2b,c assume that sexual selection remains operational on both sexes, even if one of them is clearly in the minority in the mating pool. Because this may be unrealistic for some systems, we can also opt to keep the sharp relationship of figure 2a and shift the curve leftwards towards OSR ¼ 1. Now sexual selection begins fairly accurately at OSR ¼ 1 and ceases to operate on the minority sex as soon as OSR is biased. This makes self-reinforcing sexual selection operate very efficiently: it now overrides the negatively frequencydependent pull towards biparental care at all OSR values (figure 2d: only uniparental care is possible). In contrast with figure 2d, where the smallest variations in the amount of care provided by either sex make sex roles diverge in a self-reinforcing manner, ~ curve in the opposite direction shifting the OSR-k makes the basin of attraction of biparental care wider (figure 2e). Here, sexual selection only becomes sufficiently self-reinforcing to overcome the frequencydependent pull once the OSR is strongly biased towards one sex. Such a bias is hard to reach if there is no other a priori reason why one sex should increase or decrease its parental effort (for a discussion of possibilities though, see Kokko & Jennions [54]).

769 770 771 772 773 774 775 776 777 778 779 780 781 782 783 784 785 786 787 788 789 790 791 792 793 794 795 796 797 798 799 800 801 802 803 804 805 806 807 808 809 810 811 812 813 814 815 816 817 818 819 820 821

5. DISCUSSION: WHAT DOES THIS MEAN FOR TESTING MODELS?

822 823 824 825 826 827 828 829 830 831 832

Q5

‘However, the diverse cases, contexts, models and conjectures described here indicate that positive feedback might be remarkably widespread in evolutionary and ecological processes, although its fleeting, episodic nature makes it difficult to observe directly’. Crespi [10] ‘We are thus faced with the prospect that more general analyses will reveal a dynamic quagmire [. . .] If populations remain stranded at one of a multitude of local optima, then hope of accounting for observed differences Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

7

between real world populations in terms of adaptation must quickly fade’. Schaffer & Rosenzweig [38]

833 834 835

These two quotes express two different kinds of pessimism regarding evolutionary understanding when there are alternative stable states. In the first case, the author expresses little hope for documenting selfreinforcing selection simply because the evolutionary endpoints can be reached very quickly. This is undoubtedly true, but the evolutionary endpoints still remain observable. The latter quote states that we typically only observe one endpoint at a time for any given system (contrary to systems where alternative strategies coexist in the same population). If the very same process can predict multiple equilibria that appear fundamentally different from each other, then how can we hope to test any theory, or indeed predict what will happen in a system undergoing evolutionary change in a changing environment? There is no easy answer, but in an attempt to highlight some issues, we will revisit our example of parental versus uniparental care (figure 3). Throughout, ~ relationship follows that we now assume that the OSR-k used in figure 2a. The symmetrical case (figure 3a) lacks multiple mating. Biparental care is stable, but so are two uniparental equilibria. Should multiple mating now evolve for any reason [77,78], the population shifts to a basin of attraction that leads the population to female-only care (follow the horizontal dotted arrow, then the trajectory in figure 3b leading to evolutionary endpoint B). Male care is selected against because offspring are not as often true genetic descendants of the father as they are of the mother, and sexual selection on males completes the self-reinforcing process. Q6 Now consider another environmental change that, for an unspecified reason, tends to kill males more often than females. The population consequently becomes female-biased. This new shift from figure 3b to figure 3d does not, however, produce much further change in behaviour; females remain the only carers at points B and D1 alike. One can end up from figure 3a to figure 3d via a variety of temporal routes. What happens if the extra source of male mortality arises first, and multiple mating evolves later? Now from A in figure 3a, evolution proceeds to C in figure 3c (follow the vertical dotted line, and then the evolutionary trajectory in figure 3c), uniparental care by males. There are two forces at play, both arising because the male–female difference in mortality shifts the OSR towards females. Negative feedback selects for female care (and against male care: each surviving male now has many potential female mates [54]). Simultaneously, positive feedback via sexual selection on females (owing to the OSR now being female-biased) selects against female care. In this particular example, positive feedback overrides negative feedback, and the net outcome features sex role reversal and uniparental male care. This remains unchanged when multiple mating subsequently evolves: the system now evolves from C to D2 (figure 3c,d). The overall conclusion? Depending on what happened first (increased male mortality or the evolution of multiple mating), the system has deterministically reached two totally different endpoints, either

836 837 838 839 840 841 842 843 844 845 846 847 848 849 850 851 852 853 854 855 856 857 858 859 860 861 862 863 864 865 866 867 868 869 870 871 872 873 874 875 876 877 878 879 880 881 882 883 884 885 886 887 888 889 890 891 892 893 894 895 896

ARTICLE IN PRESS 8

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

Positive feedback in evolution

897 898 899

961

multiple mating evolves (b)

(a) 0.4

962 963 964

901 902 903 904 905 906

male care duration

900

965

0.3

966 967

0.2

968

A

969 970

male mortality increases

0.1

907

B

908

0

909 910 911

(c) 0.4

(d)

912 914 915 916 917 918 919

male care duration

913

0.3

C

924 925 926 927 928

933 934 935 936 937 938 939 940 941 942 943 944 945 946 947 948 949 950 951 952 953 954 955 956 957 958 959 960

976 977 978

983 984

D1 0

0.1 0.2 0.3 female care duration

0.4

0

0.1 0.2 0.3 female care duration

985

0.4

Figure 3. Evolutionary trajectories that otherwise follow the assumptions of figure 2a but increase the mean number of males ~ ¼ 1 to n ~ ¼ 1:2 (this applies in panels b,d) and/or increase male mortality by 20% (using notaper female mating event from n tion of Kokko & Jennions [54], from m ~I ¼ m ~ O ¼ 0:01 to m ~I ¼ m ~ O ¼ 0:012; this applies in panels c,d). Straight dotted lines refer to environmental changes that shift the population from one situation, where it is originally at a stable state, to another, from which point evolution follows a trajectory to proceed to a new stable state. For clarity, we draw only two of all possible lines.

986 987 988 989 990 991 992 993 994

930 932

975

982

929 931

974

980

0.1

921 923

973

981

920 922

972

979

D2

0.2

971

uniparental female care D1 or uniparental male care D2. Is this a quagmire of a theory, then, as Schaffer & Rosenzweig [38] would call it? We have demonstrated hysteresis, a phenomenon where the temporal order of external influences matters for the endpoint reached. Only history can explain why of two related species one has evolved male-only care, the other femaleonly care, when relevant parameter values (multiple mating and sex-specific mortality) are identical between the two equilibria in figure 3d. This reminds us of the general principle that explaining the origin of a trait is not equivalent with explaining how it is currently maintained. A partial remedy is that a large number of species (or populations) may have undergone changes in a similar nature. We discussed the earlier-mentioned two routes above as if they were equally probable, but they might not be. A biologist armed with good data on actual patterns of evolutionary variation, and the relevant environmental changes associated with such variation, will be able to detect the predominant routes of evolutionary change much better than an uninformed spectator viewing myriads of possible equilibria. This abstract point is best illustrated with an example. In principle, transitions could occur between each of the four scenarios in figure 3. Some will, however, be biologically much more likely than others, and sets of parameters are unlikely to change in isolation from each other. Consider a species that initially is at solution (b) in figure 3b. If male mortality Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

increases, then it is probably more reasonable to consider that this might also impact the number of times an average female mates than to assume that this number remains unperturbed [79]. The system is therefore more likely to move from figure 3b to figure 3c than to figure 3d. That said, neither change is impossible. Encouragingly, however, both are in line with the general theory that states that an increase in male mortality can underlie a transition from female-only care to biparental care (here, the battle of negative and positive feedback stabilizes as biparentalism with more female than male care; figure 3b), or then no transition might materialize (interpretable as phylogenetic inertia; figure 3c). Good understanding of theory and data alike is required to create good predictions when these often follow the pattern ‘X favours Y when all else is equal, but because of the covarying process Z, all else is unlikely to be equal—but is Z strong enough to override?’. The entire body of theory on parenting sex roles is based on several ‘all else being equal’ type predictions; this is why the factors are not meant to be studied in isolation. With a great number of species available to study, and today’s sophisticated analysis methods that allow taking phylogenetic inertia into account, one can ask which of all possible patterns of covariation, each of them permissible in theory, predominate in nature. This should also improve our ability to predict evolutionary responses to new environmental condition: if a particular fitness valley often appears too wide to be

995 996 997 998 999 1000 1001 1002 1003 1004 1005 1006 1007 1008 1009 1010 1011 1012 1013 1014 1015 1016 1017 1018 1019 1020 1021 1022 1023 1024

ARTICLE IN PRESS Positive feedback in evolution 1025 1026 1027 1028 1029 1030 1031 1032 1033 1034 1035 1036 1037 1038

crossed by populations, it is likely to remain so on a currently changing planet too. The interplay of theory and data would be enhanced if we paid explicit attention to developing methods aimed at assessing how easily systems can shift between basins of attraction of alternative equilibria. We already mentioned drift in female choice, and complex ‘dead-ends’ in social systems. In line with this thought, phylogenetic studies could shift some of their emphasis from analysing evolutionary transitions that did happen (for parental sex role examples, see [80–83]) to evaluating the relative stability of each alternative stable state. If some are more difficult to leave than others, more transitions will enter than leave these states.

1039 1040 1041 1042 1043 1044 1045 1046 1047 1048 1049 1050 1051 1052 1053 1054 1055 1056 1057 1058 1059 1060 1061 1062 1063 1064 1065 1066 1067 1068 1069 1070 1071 1072 1073 1074 1075 1076 1077 1078 1079 1080 1081 1082 1083 1084 1085 1086 1087 1088

(a) Positive feedback leads us. . . where? The alternative stable states that a model predicts are not always well defined. In simple scenarios with, say, one locus and two alleles (‘reproduce by selfing, or outbreed’), definitions are simple: positive feedback implies that either allele can go to fixation. With continuous trait variation, changes in allele frequencies are replaced by tracking the population-wide mean value of the trait over time. There is then no (upper) boundary for trait values: examples include body size or weapon size in arms race models [15,16], or the length of a sexually selected bird’s tail in coevolutionary models of female preferences and male traits [44]. With positive feedback, the self-reinforcing process can theoretically go on forever, which is of course impossible in reality. The process may come to a halt once there is no more genetic variation for selection to operate on (which is conceptually similar to fixation of one allele in a ‘one locus, two alleles’ model), but the exact point at which this happens is arguably less interesting than the process that pushed the population along the runaway. When runaways are modelled by taking population size explicitly into account, they can also lead to extinction [84], or they may come to a natural halt if no further change is possible for some logical reason, such as zero parental care reached by one sex. Alternatively, even if there is no physical or logical boundary, a runaway process can grind to a halt because positive feedback might eventually turn negative owing to some feature of the biological interaction. Figure 3c shows an example: a biparental care equilibrium where positive and negative feedback balance out. Our example of parental sex roles, where both positive and negative feedback interact with varying strength across the OSR landscape to produce a stable outcome, should not be considered an isolated example. In the study of mate choice, an explicit discussion about the nature of equilibria has led to healthy questions concerning indirect selection on female preferences: should females still prefer a male trait once its sexually selected benefit has become balanced by a naturally selected cost [55,85– 88]? Similarly, the study of sexually antagonistic variation has benefitted from explicitly deriving predictions for the ‘standstill’ points of evolutionary arms races [89]. Whether a researcher wishes to emphasize the nonequilibrium nature of the evolutionary process, or the Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko

9

fact that traits will not spend much time very far away from equilibria [90], it always remains a core task to disentangle the various opposing forces that jointly form the causal route to each evolutionary outcome that we are trying to understand. Systems science has taught us that this can lead to emergent properties that would be hard to predict if one considered one level of organization only. Our current examples show that the same principle extends to high-level phenomena: selection on individuals interacts in a very fundamental and important way with emergent properties of populations (e.g. adult sex ratio or the level to which deleterious alleles have been purged). Discussing the relative ease or difficulty of crossing from one basin of attraction to another ought to be a key question for empiricists and theoreticians alike, if we are to explain across-species diversity as well as the common, repeatable themes in their evolutionary trajectories. We thank Andre´s Lo´pez-Sepulcre and an anonymous reviewer for comments, and the Australian Research Council and the ANU for funding.

1089 1090 1091 1092 1093 1094 1095 1096 1097 1098 1099 1100 1101 1102 1103 1104 1105 1106 1107 1108 1109 1110 1111

REFERENCES 1 De Jong, H. 2002 Modeling and simulation of genetic regulatory systems: a literature review. J. Comput. Biol. 9, 67–103. (doi:10.1089/10665270252833208) 2 Sneppen, K., Krishna, S. & Semsey, S. 2010 Simplified models of biological networks. Annu. Rev. Biophys. 39, 43–59. (doi:10.1146/annurev.biophys.093008.131241) 3 Lucas, M., Laplaze, L. & Bennett, M. J. 2010 Plant systems biology: network matters. Plant Cell Environ. 34, 535–553. (doi:10.1111/j.1365-3040.2010.02273.x) 4 Beisner, B. E., Haydon, D. T. & Cuddington, K. 2003 Alternative stable states in ecology. Front. Ecol. Environ. 1, 376 –382. (doi:10.1890/1540-9295(2003)001[0376: ASSIE]2.0.CO;2) 5 Peterrman, M. R. 1977 A simple mechanism that causes collapsing stability regions in exploited salmonid populations. J. Fish. Res. Board Can. 34, 1130–1142. (doi:10.1139/f77-170) 6 Walters, C. & Kitchell, J. F. 2001 Cultivation/depensation effects on juvenile survival and recruitment: implications for the theory of fishing. Can. J. Fish. Aquat. Sci. 58, 39–50. (doi:10.1139/f00-160) 7 Woolhouse, M. E. J., Haydon, D. T., Pearson, A. & Kitching, R. P. 1996 Failure of vaccination to prevent outbreaks of foot-and-mouth disease. Epidemiol. Infect. 116, 363 –371. (doi:10.1017/S0950268800052699) 8 Courchamp, F., Berec, L. & Gascoigne, J. 2008 Allee effects in ecology and conservation. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 9 Courchamp, F., Angulo, E., Rivalan, P., Hall, R. J., Signoret, L., Bull, L. & Meinard, Y. 2006 Rarity value and species extinction: the anthropogenic Allee effect. PLoS Biol. 4, 2405–2410. (doi:10.1371/journal.pbio. 0040415) 10 Crespi, B. J. 2004 Vicious circles: positive feedback in major evolutionary and ecological transitions. Trends Ecol. Evol. 19, 627–633. (doi:10.1016/j.tree.2004.10.001) 11 Rueffler, C., Van Dooren, T. J. M., Leimar, O. & Abrams, P. A. 2006 Disruptive selection and then what? Trends Ecol. Evol. 21, 238–245. (doi:10.1016/j. tree.2006.03.003) 12 Ackermann, M. & Doebeli, M. 2004 Evolution of niche width and adaptive diversification. Evolution 58, 2599 –2612.

1112 1113 1114 1115 1116 1117 1118 1119 1120 1121 1122 1123 1124 1125 1126 1127 1128 1129 1130 1131 1132 1133 1134 1135 1136 1137 1138 1139 1140 1141 1142 1143 1144 1145 1146 1147 1148 1149 1150 1151 1152

ARTICLE IN PRESS 10 1153 1154 1155 1156 1157 1158 1159 1160 1161 1162 1163 1164 1165 1166 1167 1168 1169 1170 1171 1172 1173 1174 1175 1176 1177 1178 1179 1180 1181 1182 1183 1184 1185 1186 1187 1188 1189 1190 1191 1192 1193 1194 1195 1196 1197 1198 1199 1200 1201 1202 1203 1204 1205 1206 1207 1208 1209 1210 1211 1212 1213 1214 1215 1216

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko Positive feedback in evolution

13 Keller, L. F. & Waller, D. M. 2002 Inbreeding effects in wild populations. Trends Ecol. Evol. 17, 230 –241. (doi:10.1016/S0169-5347(02)02489-8) 14 Fisher, R. A. 1941 Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Annu. Eugen. 11, 53–63. (doi:10. 1111/j.1469-1809.1941.tb02272.x) 15 Parker, G. A. 1979 Sexual selection and sexual conflict. In Sexual selection and reproductive competition in insects (eds M. S. Blum & N. A. Blum), pp. 123 –166. New York, NY: Academic Press. 16 Parker, G. 2006 Sexual conflict over mating and fertilization: an overview. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 361, 235– 259. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2005.1785) 17 Kokko, H. & Ots, I. 2006 When not to avoid inbreeding. Evolution 60, 467 –475. 18 Lande, R. & Schemske, D. W. 1985 The evolution of selffertilization and inbreeding depression in plants. I. Genetic models. Evolution 39, 24–40. (doi:10.2307/2408514) 19 Crnokrak, P. & Barrett, S. C. H. 2002 Purging the genetic load: a review of the experimental evidence. Evolution 56, 2347–2358. 20 de Jong, T. & Klinkhamer, P. 2005 Evolutionary ecology of plant reproductive strategies. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 21 Barrett, C. H. & Harder, L. D. 1996 Ecology and evolution of plant mating. Trends Ecol. Evol. 11, 73 –79. (doi:10.1016/0169-5347(96)81046-9) 22 Goodwillie, C., Kalisz, S. & Eckert, C. G. 2005 The evolutionary enigma of mixed mating systems in plants: occurrence, theoretical explanations, and empirical evidence. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Evol. Syst. 36, 47–79. (doi:10. 1146/annurev.ecolsys.36.091704.175539) 23 Lane, J. E., Boutin, S., Gunn, M. R., Slate, J. & Coltman, D. W. 2007 Genetic relatedness of mates does not predict patterns of parentage in North American red squirrels. Anim. Behav. 74, 611 –619. (doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2006.12.017) 24 De de Luca, P. & Cocroft, R. B. 2008 The effects of age and relatedness on mating patterns in thornbug treehoppers: inbreeding avoidance or inbreeding tolerance? Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 62, 1869–1875. (doi:10.1007/ s00265-008-0616-2) 25 Bilde, T., Lubin, Y., Smith, D., Schneider, J. M. & Maklakov, A. A. 2005 The transition to social inbred mating systems in spiders: role of inbreeding tolerance in a subsocial predecessor. Evolution 59, 160 –174. 26 Guevara-Fiore, P., Rosenqvist, G. & Watt, P. J. 2010 Inbreeding level does not induce female discrimination between sibs and unrelated males in guppies. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 64, 1601 –1607. (doi:10.1007/s00265010-0973-5) 27 Hughes, W. O. H., Oldroyd, B. P., Beekman, M. & Ratnieks, F. L. W. 2008 Ancestral monogamy shows kin selection is key to the evolution of eusociality. Science 320, 1213–1216. (doi:10.1126/science.1156108) 28 Cornwallis, C. K., West, S. A., Davis, K. E. & Griffin, A. S. 2010 Promiscuity and the evolutionary transition to complex societies. Nature 466, 969 –972. (doi:10. 1038/nature09335) 29 Wilson, E. O. & Ho¨lldobler, B. 2005 Eusociality: origin and consequences. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 102, 13 367–13 371. (doi:10.1073/pnas.0505858102) 30 Foster, K. R. 2009 A defense of sociobiology. Cold Spring Harb. Symp. Quant. Biol. 74, 419–426. (doi:10.1101/ sqb.2009.74.041) 31 Axelrod, R. & Hamilton, W. D. 1981 The evolution of cooperation. Science 211, 1390–1396. (doi:10.1126/ science.7466396) 32 El Mouden, C., West, S. A. & Gardner, A. 2010 The enforcement of cooperation by policing. Evolution 64, 2139–2152. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

33 Kokko, H., Johnstone, R. A. & Clutton-Brock, T. H. 2001 The evolution of cooperative breeding through group augmentation. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 268, 187 –196. (doi:10.1098/rspb.2000.1349) 34 Eshel, I. & Shaked, A. 2001 Partnership. J. Theor. Biol. 208, 457 –474. (doi:10.1006/jtbi.2000.2232) 35 Garay, J. 2009 Cooperation in defence against a predator. J. Theor. Biol. 357, 45–51. (doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2008.11.010) 36 Aanen, D. K. & Hoekstra, R. F. 2007 The evolution of obligate mutualism: if you can’t beat ’em, join ’em. Trends Ecol. Evol. 22, 506 –509. (doi:10.1016/j.tree. 2007.08.007) 37 Abrams, P. A. 2000 The evolution of predator– prey interactions: theory and evidence. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 31, 79–105. (doi:10.1146/annurev.ecolsys.31.1.79) 38 Schaffer, W. M. & Rosenzweig, M. L. 1977 Selection for optimal life histories. II: Multiple equilibria and the evolution of alternative reproductive strategies. Ecology 58, 60–72. (doi:10.2307/1935108) 39 Parker, G. A., Baker, R. R. & Smith, V. G. F. 1972 The origin and evolution of gamete dimorphism and the male– female phenomenon. J. Theor. Biol. 36, 181–198. (doi:10.1016/0022-5193(72)90007-0) 40 Lessells, C. M., Snook, R. R. & Hosken, D. J. 2009 The evolutionary origin and maintenance of sperm: selection for a small, motile gamete mating type. In Sperm biology: an evolutionary perspective (eds T. R. Birkhead, D. J. Hosken & S. Pitnick), pp. 43–67. New York, NY: Academic Press. 41 Parker, G. A. 1982 Why are there so many tiny sperm? Sperm competition and the maintenance of two sexes. J. Theor. Biol. 96, 281 –294. (doi:10.1016/00225193(82)90225-9) 42 Lehtonen, J. & Kokko, H. 2010 Two roads to two sexes: unifying gamete competition and gamete limitation in a single model of anisogamy evolution. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 65, 445 –459. (doi:10.1007/s00265-010-1116-8) 43 Fisher, R. A. 1930 The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 44 Mead, L. S. & Arnold, S. J. 2004 Quantitative genetic models of sexual selection. Trends Ecol. Evol. 19, 264 –271. (doi:10.1016/j.tree.2004.03.003) 45 Higashi, M., Takimoto, G. & Yamamura, N. 1999 Sympatric speciation by sexual selection. Nature 402, 523 –526. (doi:10.1038/990087) 46 van Doorn, G. S., Dieckmann, U. & Weissing, F. J. 2004 Sympatric speciation by sexual selection: a critical reevaluation. Am. Nat. 163, 709 –725. (doi:10.1086/383619) 47 Weissing, F. J., Edelaar, P. & van Doorn, G. S. 2010 Adaptive speciation theory: a conceptual review. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 65, 461– 480. (doi:10.1007/s00265-0101125-7) 48 Lande, R. 1981 Models of speciation by sexual selection on polygenic characters. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 78, 3721–3725. (doi:10.1073/pnas.78.6.3721) 49 Prum, R. O. 2010 The Lande –Kirkpatrick mechanism is the null model of evolution by intersexual selection: implications for meaning, honesty, and design in intersexual signals. Evolution 64, 3085–3100. (doi:10.1111/ j.1558-5646.2010.01054.x) 50 Pomiankowski, A., Iwasa, Y. & Nee, S. 1991 The evolution of costly mate preferences. I. Fisher and biased mutation. Evolution 45, 1422–1430. 51 Iwasa, Y., Pomiankowski, A. & Nee, S. 1991 The evolution of costly mate preferences. II. The ‘handicap’ principle. Evolution 45, 1431–1442. (doi:10.2307/ 2409890) 52 Iwasa, Y. & Pomiankowski, A. 1995 Continual change in mate preferences. Nature 377, 420 –422. (doi:10.1038/ 377420a0)

1217 1218 1219 1220 1221 1222 1223 1224 1225 1226 1227 1228 1229 1230 1231 1232 1233 1234 1235 1236 1237 1238 1239 1240 1241 1242 1243 1244 1245 1246 1247 1248 1249 1250 1251 1252 1253 1254 1255 1256 1257 1258 1259 1260 1261 1262 1263 1264 1265 1266 1267 1268 1269 1270 1271 1272 1273 1274 1275 1276 1277 1278 1279 1280

ARTICLE IN PRESS Positive feedback in evolution 1281 1282 1283 1284 1285 1286 1287 1288 1289 1290 1291 1292 1293 1294 1295 1296 1297 1298 1299 1300 1301 1302 1303 1304 1305 1306 1307 1308 1309 1310 1311 1312 1313 1314 1315 1316 1317 1318 1319 1320 1321 1322 1323 1324 1325 1326 1327 1328 1329 1330 1331 1332 1333 1334 1335 1336 1337 1338 1339

53 Kokko, H., Brooks, R., McNamara, J. M. & Houston, A. I. 2002 The sexual selection continuum. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 269, 1331–1340. (doi:10.1098/rspb.2002.2020) 54 Kokko, H. & Jennions, M. D. 2008 Parental investment, sexual selection and sex ratios. J. Evol. Biol. 21, 919 –948. (doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2008.01540.x) 55 Cameron, E., Day, T. & Rowe, L. 2003 Sexual conflict and indirect benefits. J. Evol. Biol. 16, 1055–1060. (doi:10.1046/j.1420-9101.2003.00584.x) 56 Friedl, T. W. P. & Klump, G. M. 2005 Sexual selection in the lek-breeding European treefrog: body size, chorus attendance, random mating and good genes. Anim. Behav. 70, 1141–1154. (doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2005.01.017) 57 Garcia, C. M. & Ramirez, E. 2005 Evidence that sensory traps can evolve into honest signals. Nature 434, 501 –505. (doi:10.1038/nature03363) 58 Fuller, R. C., Houle, D. & Travis, J. 2005 Sensory bias as an explanation for the evolution of mate preferences. Am. Nat. 166, 437–446. (doi:10.1086/444443) 59 Johnstone, R. A., Reynolds, J. D. & Deutsch, J. C. 1996 Mutual mate choice and sex differences in choosiness. Evolution 50, 1382–1391. (doi:10.2307/2410876) 60 Prudic, K. L., Jeon, C., Cao, H. & Monteiro, A. 2010 Developmental plasticity in sexual roles of butterfly species drives mutual sexual ornamentation. Science 331, 73–75. (doi:10.1126/science.1197114) 61 Hammerstein, P. & Parker, G. A. 1987 Sexual selection: games between the sexes. In Sexual selection: testing the alternatives (eds J. W. Bradbury & M. B. Andersson), pp. 119 –142. Chichester, UK: Wiley. 62 Houston, A. I., Sze´kely, T. & McNamara, J. M. 2005 Conflict between parents over care. Trends Ecol. Evol. 20, 33–38. (doi:10.1016/j.tree.2004.10.008) 63 Motro, U. 1991 Avoiding inbreeding and sibling competition: the evolution of sexual dimorphism for dispersal. Am. Nat. 137, 108 –115. (doi:10.1086/285148) 64 Perrin, N. & Mazalov, V. 1999 Dispersal and inbreeding avoidance. Am. Nat. 154, 282–292. (doi:10.1086/ 303236) 65 Kokko, H. & Wong, B. B. M. 2007 What determines sex roles in mate searching? Evolution 61, 1162 –1175. (doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2007.00090.x) 66 Trivers, R. L. 1972 Parental investment and sexual selection. In Sexual selection and the descent of man 1871–1971 (ed. B. Campbell), pp. 136 –179. Chicago, IL: Aldine Publishing Company. 67 Dawkins, R. 1976 The selfish gene. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 68 Maynard Smith, J. 1982 Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 69 Webb, J. N., Houston, A. I., McNamara, J. M. & Sze´kely, T. 1999 Multiple patterns of parental care. Anim. Behav. 58, 983–993. (doi:10.1006/anbe.1999.1215) 70 Queller, D. C. 1997 Why do females care more than males? Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 264, 1555–1557. (doi:10. 1098/rspb.1997.0216) 71 Houston, A. I. & McNamara, J. M. 2005 John Maynard Smith and the importance of consistency in evolutionary game theory. Biol. Philos. 20, 933–950. (doi:10.1007/ s10539-005-9016-4) 72 Jennions, M. D. & Kokko, H. 2010 Sexual selection. In Evolutionary behavioral ecology (eds D. F. Westneat & C. W. Fox), pp. 343 –364. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

J. Lehtonen & H. Kokko 11

73 Emlen, S. T. & Oring, L. W. 1977 Ecology, sexual selection, and the evolution of mating systems. Science 197, 215 –223. (doi:10.1126/science.327542) 74 Klug, H., Heuschele, J., Jennions, M. D. & Kokko, H. 2010 The mismeasurement of sexual selection. J. Evol. Biol. 23, 447 –462. (doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2009. 01921.x) 75 Fitze, P. S. & Le Galliard, F. 2008 Operational sex ratio, sexual conflict and the intensity of sexual selection. Ecol. Lett. 11, 432 –439. (doi:10.1111/j.1461-0248.2008. 01158.x) 76 Kokko, H. & Johnstone, R. A. 2002 Why is mutual mate choice not the norm? Operational sex ratios, sex roles, and the evolution of sexually dimorphic and monomorphic signalling. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 357, 319 –330. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.0926) 77 Arnqvist, G. & Nilsson, T. 2000 The evolution of polyandry: multiple mating and female fitness in insects. Anim. Behav. 60, 145 –164. (doi:10.1006/anbe.2000.1446) 78 Jennions, M. D. & Petrie, M. 2000 Why do females mate mutiply? A review of the genetic benefits. Biol. Rev. 75, 21– 64. (doi:10.1017/S0006323199005423) 79 Kokko, H. & Mappes, J. 2005 Sexual selection when fertilization is not guaranteed. Evolution 59, 1876–1885. 80 Goodwin, N. B., Balshine-Earn, S. & Reynolds, J. D. 1998 Evolutionary transitions in parental care in cichlid fish. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 265, 2265–2272. (doi:10. 1098/rspb.1998.0569) 81 Gonzalez-Voyer, A., Fitzpatrick, J. L. & Kolm, N. 2008 Sexual selection determines parental care patterns in cichlid fishes. Evolution 62, 2015–2026. (doi:10.1111/j. 1558-5646.2008.00426.x) 82 Olson, V. A., Liker, A., Freckleton, R. P. & Sze´kely, T. 2008 Parental conflict in birds: comparative analyses of offspring development, ecology and mating opportunities. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 275, 301– 307. (doi:10. 1098/rspb.2007.1395) 83 Olson, V. A., Webb, T. J., Freckleton, R. P. & Sze´kely, T. 2009 Are parental care trade-offs in shorebirds driven by parental investment or sexual selection? J. Evol. Biol. 22, 672 –682. (doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2009.01701.x) 84 Dieckmann, U. & Metz, J. A. J. 2006 Surprising evolutionary predictions from enhanced ecological realism. Theor. Popul. Biol. 69, 263 –281. (doi:10.1016/j.tpb. 2005.12.001) 85 Brooks, R. 2000 Negative genetic correlation between male sexual attractiveness and survival. Nature 406, 67– 70. (doi:10.1038/35017552) 86 Hall, D. W., Kirkpatrick, M. & West, B. 2000 Runaway sexual selection when female preferences are directly selected. Evolution 54, 1862–1869. 87 Kokko, H., Jennions, M. D. & Brooks, R. 2006 Unifying and testing models of sexual selection. Ann. Rev. Ecol. Evol. Syst. 37, 43–66. (doi:10.1146/annurev.ecolsys.37. 091305.110259) 88 Greenspoon, P. B. & Otto, S. P. 2009 Evolution by Fisherian sexual selection in diploids. Evolution 63, 1076 –1083. (doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2008.00606.x) 89 Arnqvist, G. & Rowe, L. 2002 Antagonistic coevolution between the sexes in a group of insects. Nature 415, 787 –789. 90 Hammerstein, P. 1996 Darwinian adaptation, population genetics and the streetcar theory of evolution. J. Math. Biol. 34, 511 –532. (doi:10.1007/BF02409748)

1345 1346 1347 1348 1349 1350 1351 1352 1353 1354 1355 1356 1357 1358 1359 1360 1361 1362 1363 1364 1365 1366 1367 1368 1369 1370 1371 1372 1373 1374 1375 1376 1377 1378 1379 1380 1381 1382 1383 1384 1385 1386 1387 1388 1389 1390 1391 1392 1393 1394 1395 1396 1397 1398 1399 1400 1401 1402 1403

1340

1404

1341

1405

1342

1406

1343

1407

1344

1408

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2011) rstb20110177—14/10/11—13:59–Copy Edited by: J. Tamilselvam

Positive feedback and alternative stable states in ...

populations)—can drive a population extinct via an. Allee effect. Here .... mediate selfing rate [20,21], which is hard to explain if positive feedback is the only ...

214KB Sizes 1 Downloads 161 Views

Recommend Documents

Mo_Jianhua_Asilomar15_Limited Feedback in Multiple-Antenna ...
Retrying... Mo_Jianhua_Asilomar15_Limited Feedback in Multiple-Antenna Systems with One-Bit Quantization.pdf. Mo_Jianhua_Asilomar15_Limited Feedback ...

United States Edition (Alternative Etext Formats)
... and Design with UML This revision offers a crisp, clear explanation of the basics of ... An integrated case study threads throughout the ... Computer Architecture- A Quantitave Approch · Computer Networking: A Top-Down Approach, 6Th Edn.

Stable Marriage and Search Frictions
Jul 5, 2012 - Define x(m,m) = 1− ∑ w∈W x(m,w) and x(w,w) = 1− ∑ m∈M x(m,w). .... Definition (Steady State Matching) .... Utilities given by the bi-matrix w1.

Beyond Red States and Blue States in Cognitive Science.pdf
complexity of the universe as a whole. In the end, it seems that our difference with Dietrich is. that we are somewhat more optimistic about the prospect of ...

Conferencing and Feedback - ciclt.net
Feb 13, 2013 - structured process for facilitating ... give actionable information. ... only factual information about how one is progressing in relation to a goal.

Conferencing and Feedback - ciclt.net
Feb 13, 2013 - Conferencing and feedback are required components of the. Teacher Keys Effectiveness System (TKES) and the Leader Keys. Effectiveness ...

Systematic study of the stable states of C , Si , Ge , and Sn ... - naomib
todetached electron spectrometry LPES and threshold pho- todetachment with ...... 48 D. Calabrese, A. M. Covington, J. S. Thompson, R. W. Ma- rawar, and J. W. ...

Systematic study of the stable states of C , Si , Ge , and Sn ... - naomib
A Lumonics HD-300 dye laser is pumped by the second harmonic of a 10-Hz ...... Different storage rings e.g., ELISA in Aarhus, Denmark may in fact enable ...

Systematic study of the stable states of C , Si , Ge , and Sn ... - naomib
been extensively studied with a variety of experimental tech- niques 3. Most early ..... tinuously flushing the laser housing with cool nitrogen gas. A calibration ...

Verum Focus in Alternative Semantics
Jan 9, 2016 - The relevant empirical domain is also a matter of controversy. • The most ... free head features of Φ with the occupant of Φ (complementizer, finite verb). e. A feature ..... (33) A: I was wondering how much food to buy for tonight.

Complementary inputs and the existence of stable outcomes in large ...
Jun 22, 2017 - However, Azevedo and Hatfield's (2013) conditions do not define a maximal domain for the existence of stable outcomes in large two-sided ...

A simple test for alternative states in ecological ... - Wiley Online Library
May 31, 2013 - monitoring; Pteridium aquilinum; Resilience; .... linear mixed models, even including monitoring pro- .... monitoring structure (plot/block/site).

Procedurally Fair and Stable Matching
stable matchings in which he/she is not matched to his/her best partner in the reduced set of .... is better off as well, then we would expect this mutually beneficial “trade” to be carried out, rendering the given ... private schools and univers

Stable and efficient coalitional networks - Springer Link
Sep 9, 2012 - made to the coalitional network needs the consent of both the deviating players and their original coalition partners. Requiring the consent of ...

Delayed versus immediate feedback in children's and ...
computer in both the delayed and immediate conditions, rather than simply ..... regularly scheduled social science classes in the students' classroom, during school ..... Salary; payment for an office; compensation ... Of the nature of a network.

Feedback Consistency Effects in Visual and Auditory ...
items. Finally, in Experiment 3 we test the idea that feedback consistency effects in the auditory domain are generally more stable because of the fact that, in the ...

Feedback and Interference Alignment in Networks
Sep 28, 2011 - where ρ∗ is the solution between 0 and 1 such that .... pared to the aggregated remaining BSs. ... backhaul between BSs of different cells.

Feedback Consistency Effects in Visual and Auditory ...
Because such databases of lexical decision and naming perfor- mance contain a large ...... database analysis of reading aloud and lexical decision. However,.

Procedurally Fair and Stable Matching
The first procedurally fair and stable matching mechanism we consider, called ... P(m) = w3 w2 mw1 ... w4 indicates that m prefers w3 to w2 and he prefers .... and uses survey data to analyze various hypotheses on different aspects of ...

Download Horse and Stable Management ...
Download Horse and Stable Management. (Incorporating ... The BHS Complete Manual of Stable Management · The Course Companion for BHS Stages I & II.