Stative Quantity E. Matthew Husband Michigan State University April, 2007 Predicates don’t always behave the way they should, a variable behavior phenomenon: (1)

Individual-level predicates? a. Francis is occasionally blond. b. Suddenly, Lynn knew the answer.

(2)

Stage-level predicates? a. Sam goes jogging after work. b. Hakeem plays basketball for a living.

(Fernald, 1999)

A quote: “If a distinction between stage-level and individual-level predicates is operative in natural language, it cannot be a distinction that is made in the lexicon of a language once and for all.” (Kratzer (1995), p. 125-126) Two seemingly separate questions: • Q: If the stage-level/individual-level distinction is not made in the lexicon, what component (if any) is the distinction based in? • Q: How might inner aspect play a role in stative predicates? An overview: 1. Give a brief overview of the stage-level/individual-level distinction, noting its interaction with inner aspect. 2. Review an approach to inner aspect in eventive predicates, focusing particularly on its composition of the internal argument which accesses its properties. 3. Propose that the stage-level/individual-level distinction arises do to aspectual structure in stative predicates through a compositional process which also accesses internal argument properties. Some assumptions: • Neo-constructionist grammar (Exoskeletal System, Distributed Morphology, etc. (Borer, 2005a,b; Marantz, 1997; Harley and Noyer, 1999)) The basic structure of nominals: [DP [#P [ClP [√P . . . 1

The basic structure of the clause: [EP [T P [SP [AspP/F S P [√P . . . 1 • Variable Identification (an extension of Event Identification (Kratzer, 1996)) (3)

Variable Identification: β, αtαt → β, αt Mary sneezed. VoiceP λe∃x.sneeze(e)&V oice(e, M ary(x))

Voice λxλe.sneeze(e)&V oice(e, x) (by Event Ident.)

DP ∃x.M ary(x)

Voice λxλe.V oice(e, x)

VP λe.sneeze(e)

The intuition and goal: Suppose functional morphology is freely combined in the syntax, subject only to a universal hierarchy of projection, and suppose previous work in the syntax of aspect. Functional morphemes which give rise to quantity interpretations then should combine with a multitude of categories, including nominals and events (Borer, 2005a,b) but also adjectives, states, and possibly others. The interpretation of quantity in each of these domains may appear different: count/mass in nominals, telicity in events, but also closed/open scales in adjectives and stage-level/individual-level distinction in states. For the particular case of states, given the universal hierarchy of projection, quantity interpretation should share many of the properties found in the case of events.

1

Stage-level and individual-level predicates (4)

a. b.

Firemen are altruistic. Firemen are available.

(individual-level) (stage-level)

The examples in (4) demonstrate classic examples of stage-level and individual-level predicates (Kratzer, 1995). Two properties of focus today: Spatiotemporal Modification (5,6) and Subject Interpretation. (5)

a. # Firemen are altruistic in the station/on Thursday. b. Firemen are available in the station/on Thursday.

(6)

a. # When firemen are altruistic, they are very helpful. b. When firemen are available, they are at the station.2

1

The structures here are taken from Borer (2005a,b). DP = Determiner Phrase, #P = Number Phrase, ClP = Classifier Phrase, EP = Event Phrase, TP = Tense Phrase, SP = Stative Phrase, AspP = Aspectual Phrase, FS P = √ Functional Shell Phrase, P = Root Phrase 2 I will try to be consistant on noting judgments: * = ungrammatical, ? = ungrammatical but weaker, # = unavailable reading/pragmatically odd

2

Spatiotemporal Modification: Individual-level predicates cannot be modified by spatiotemporal modifiers (5) or act as the restrictor of when-conditional (6). Subject Interpretation: Subjects of individual-level predicates receive generic interpretation only (4a) while subjects of stage-level predicates can receive either generic or existential interpretations (4b).

1.1

Conditioned constructions

Additionally, several different constructions are sensitive to the stage-level/individual-level distinction, including There-insertion (7), absolute constructions (8), the copula in Spanish (9), and quantifier split in German (10). (7)

There-insertion a. * There are firemen altruistic. b. There are firemen avalible.

(8)

Absolute constructions a. Having unusually long arms, John can touch the ceiling. → If John has unusually long arms, he can touch the ceiling. b. Standing on a chair, John can touch the ceiling. → If John is standing on a chair, he can touch the ceiling.

(9)

Copula in Spanish a. Bombeiros sao/*estao altruistas. Firemen ser/estar altruistic. ‘Firemen are altruistic.’ b. Bombeiros *sao/estao disponiveis. Firemen ser/estar available. ‘Firemen are available.’

(10)

(Schmitt, 1992)

Quantifier split in German a. * Lehrer wissen das viele. teachers know this many. ‘As for teachers, many of them know this.’ b. Lehrer haben uns viele geholfen. teachers have us many helped. ‘As for teachers, many of them helped us.’

1.2

(Kratzer, 1995)

Interactions with inner aspect

Finally, an important observation is that the stage-level/individual-level distinction interacts with inner aspect.

3

(11)

a. John b. John c. # John d. John

is is is is

intelligent. happy. being intelligent. being happy.

(12)

a. Concrete is hard. b. Ponds are empty. c. # Concrete hardened. d. Ponds emptied.

(individual-level stative) (stage-level stative) (individual-level eventive) (stage-level eventive) (individual-level stative) (stage-level stative) (individual-level eventive) (stage-level eventive)

Importantly, (11c) and (12c) do not have individual-level interpretations. Generalizing from these cases, individual-level predicates are barred in eventive contexts, but stage-level predicates are permitted in stative contexts. This interaction was noted in Fernald (2000) who suggested that without it, the stage-level/individuallevel distinction would collapse with inner aspect. I will refer to this as Fernald’s Generalization. (13)

Fernald’s Generalization States: stage-level/ individual-level Events: stage-level/*individual-level

Some questions: 1. Why are individual-level predicates barred from eventive contexts? 2. Why are stage-level predicates permitted in stative contexts?

2

Inner aspect in events

A reminder about the distribution of temporal modifiers for the classic view of inner aspect (Dowty, 1979). (14)

a. b. c. d.

State: Activity: Accomplishment: Achievement:

John John John John

loved the race (for 10 years/#in 10 years). ran (for 2 hours/#in 2 hours.) ran the race (#for 34 minutes/in 34 minutes.) won the race (#for 10 minutes/in 10 minutes.)

The traditional explaination: Having no inherent endpoint, the state (14a) and activity (14b) cannot be modified by in X time. The accomplishment (14c) and achievement (14d) predicates both have inherent endpoints, and can be modified by in X time which modifies the endpoint.

4

2.1

Inner aspect and the internal argument

The differences between activity and accomplishment predicates is of particular interest here as the distinction between them often follows from properties of their internal argument. (15)

Non-quantity argument a. John built houses (#in three months). b. Mary drank beer (#in three hours).

(16)

Quantity argument a. John built the houses (in three months). b. Mary drank three beers (in three hours).

When the internal arguement is non-quantity, an activity (atelic) predicate occurs. When the internal argument is quantity, an accomplishment (telic) predicate occurs.

2.2

Interpretation of quantity

There is a long tradition of linking quantity/homogenity to telic/atelic predicates respectively (Verkuyl, 1972; Dowty, 1979; Verkuyl, 1993). (17)

a. Quantity: P is quantity iff P is not homogeneous. b. Homogeneous: P is homogeneous iff P is cumulative and divisive. i. Cumulative: P is cumulative iff ∀x, y[P (x)&P (y) → P (x ∪ y)] ii. Divisive: P is divisive iff ∀x[P (x) → ∃y[P (y)&y < x]]&∀x, y[P (x)&P (y)&y < x → P (x − y)] 3

States (14a) and activities (14b) are homogeneous, whereas accomplishments (14c) and achievements (14d) are quantity. In (15) and (16), the homogeneity/quantity of the predicate is derived from the homogeneity/quantity of the internal argument respectively. Bare plural and mass nouns for a class of homogeneous nominals (18) while other nominals are argued to have quantity (19), reflecting the mass/count distinction. (18)

Non-quantity nominals a. water, sand, concrete, furnature, . . . b. houses, apples, ponds, dogs, . . .

(19)

Quantity nominals a. the/a house, the/a water, the/a building, . . . b. the houses, the apples, the dogs, . . . c. more than three houses, over three oceans, . . .

3

These definitions are taken from Borer (2005b).

5

Assuming functional structure yeilds these differences in quantity, Borer (2005a) suggests that #P is the locus of quantity for nominals. When #P is projected, the nominal is interpreted as having quantifiable divisions. (20) (21)

[[#]] = λyλx.quantity(x, y) Composition of Quantity Nominal ... D

#P λx.apples(x)&quantity(x, three)

three

# λyλx.apples(x)&quantity(x, y) (by Var. Ident.) # λyλx.quantity(x, y)

NP λx.apples(x) .

Following Schmitt (1996); Borer (2005b) and many others (see Rosen (1999) for a review), movement of a quantity internal argument to a projection higher than the VP, here AspP, licenses the event to have quantifiable divisions.4 (22) (23)

[[Asp]] = λxλe.quantity(e, x) Composition of Quantity Eventive5 AspP λe.eat (e)&quantity(e, threeapples)&Int (e, threeapples)

DP three apples

3

Asp λxλe.eat (e)&quantity(e, x)&Int (e, threeapples) (by Var. Ident.) Asp λxλe.quantity(e, x)

VP λe.eat (e)&Int(e, threeapples)

Inner aspect in states

Continuing to assume that functional structure is licensing interpretations, I will take the basic structure for stative predicates to be the following: Statives are non-atomic, a property which results from the projection of functional structure SP.6 4

Given that non-quantity arguments must also check case, Borer (2005b) posits a projection FS P which occurs in complementary distribution with AspP. I will not be discussing FS P here in the analysis, also its use should be apparent. 5 Int(e,x) is used here to indicate the internal argument. I leave aside questions concerning the thematic relation carried by the internal argument. 6 I assume that states differ from events through a functional projection, SP, which stativizes the predicate and preempts verbalization. Linking the state/event distinction to atomicity (Bach, 1986), I tentively suggest that SP composes a nonatomic property of events into the event description.

6

(24)

Composition of Stative ...

T

√ SP λe. (e)&nonatomic(e) . . . S λe.nonatomic(e)

√ VP/AP λα. (α) . . .

We will be paying closer attention to adjectival statives, although verbal statives are not exempt from this analysis.

3.1

Adjectival scales

Kennedy and McNally (2005) discuss scale structure in the semantics of adjectives. The distribution of degree modifiers argues for at least two classes of adjectives: closed scale (25) and open scale (26).7 (25)

Closed scale adjectives a. The glass is half/mostly/completely full. b. Her eyes were half/most of the way/completely closed. c. These images are half/mostly/completely invisible.

(26)

Open scale adjectives a. # The rope is half/mostly/completely long. b. # A 15-year old horse is half/mostly/completely old. c. # That car was half/mostly/completely expensive.

3.2

Scalar representation in syntax

Given the system proposed here, closed scale representation is the result of the projection of functional structure. In the case of adjectives, the functional structure licensed by the degree modifier, here DegP, is suggested to yeild quantity interpretations.8 (1) (2)

Nonatomic: P is nonatomic iff ∀x∃y[P (x) → [P (y)&y < x]] [[S]] = λe.nonatomic(e)

The correct representation for the stativizing funtional morpheme and its projection within the universal hierarchy are left for further research, though pointed out in Borer (2005b), given the existence of transitive states SP must project between TP and whatever functional structure licenses internal arguments. 7 A test showing open scale interpretation makes use of the degree modifier very (very #full/*closed/#invisible vs. very long/old/expensive). 8 Whether DegP as used here can be considered the same functional projection proposed in Kennedy (1997) is dependent on several other factors, not the least being concerned with the ontological assumptions of adjectives and the position of degree modifiers for open vs. closed scales, and left for future work.

7

(27) (28)

[[Deg]] = λdλx.quantity(x, d) Composition of Quantity Adjectival DegP λx.f ull(x)&quantity(x, completely)

Deg λdλx.f ull(x)&quantity(x, d)

completely

Deg λdλx.quantity(x, d)

√ f ull λx.f ull(x)

Given that traditionally closed scale adjectives do not necessarily need an overt degree modifier, I suggest that the adjective itself can license the projection of DegP in the syntax.9 (29)

Composition of Quantity Adjectival DegP λx.f ull(x)&quantity(x, f ull) √

Deg λdλx.f ull(x)&quantity(x, d)

f ull

Deg λdλx.quantity(x, d)

3.3

t√f ull λx.f ull(x)

Interpretation of scale structure

Consider again our definitions of quantity (17). Open scales are homogeneous,10 but closed scales are not necessarily so. At their maximum/minimum, closes scales fail to be divisive because they do not have a subpart (i.e. they fail the ∀x[P (x) → ∃y[P (y)&y < x]] condition).

(30)

closed scale open scale

max/min degree yes no

cumulative √ √

divisive * √

Consider the interpretation of scale structure and quantity. Closed scale adjectives have quantifiable divisions whereas open scale adjectives do not. Thus degree modifiers such as completely, half, etc. force the representation to have a division in it - a maximum or minimum value on the scale. 9 Kennedy (2001); Kennedy and McNally (2005) make several claims about the polysemy of adjectives between closed and open scales, for instance dry (very dry (open scale)/completely dry (closed scale)). Assuming the system put forth here, the scale structure of adjectives is interpreted by the grammar through a functional projection and polysemy arises as adjectival roots are embedded under this functional projection. The acceptablility of the resulting structure then depends not on the grammar but on the extent that the conceptual system allows coercion of the adjectival concept to be of the scale dictated by the grammar. When these clash, unacceptability arises. 10 This is especially true if the language faculty makes use of universal density of measurement as proposed by Fox and Hackl (2006).

8

3.4

Quantity in statives

The interpretation of scale structure in adjectives appears to condition the type of predicate interpretation a stative receives to the extent that they are closed or open scale. Quantity adjectives yeild stage-level interpretations while non-quantity adjectives do not.11 (31)

Open a. b. c.

scale states People are intelligent. Rocks are hard. Roads are wide.

(32)

Closed scale states a. People are happy. b. Ponds are empty. c. Ropes are straight.

Subject Interp. Γ/*∃ Γ/*∃ Γ/*∃ Γ/ ∃ Γ/ ∃ Γ/ ∃

Spatiotemp. Mod. # # # √ √ √

This seems to also be the case for verbal statives as well. When the internal argument is quantity, stage-level interpretation results, but when the internal argument is non-quantity, the predicate receives individual-level interpretation. (33)

Non-quantity argument a. People own houses. b. Women like older men.

Subject Interp. Γ/*∃ Γ/*∃

(34)

Quantity argument a. People own the house. b. Women like that older man.

Γ/∃ Γ/∃

Spatiotemp. Mod. # # √ √

The Spanish copula also appears to be conditioned by the scale structure of the adjective.12 ,13 11 These data become sharper when completely or very is put before the adjective, forcing a closed or open scale reading. Since some adjectives resist coercion into closed or open scale interpretation, completely and very are left off from the data set. Note however that this result only emphisizes the point that functional structure for quantity in one domain can lead to difference in another, here realized as closed/open scales and a distinction between stage-level and individual-level interpretation, similar to what is seen in eventives with count/mass internal arguments. 12 In Spanish completamente (completely) was used to test for closed scale interpretation of the adjectives. 13 My Spanish informant also provided the following data concering ser /estar and its relation to English progressive/participle forms.

(1)

a. Soy aburrido. ser bored. ‘I am boring.’ b. Estoy aburrido. estar bored. ‘I am bored.’

These facts also link up to the stage-level/individual-level distinction. (1a) is individual-level, while (1b) is stagelevel.

9

(35)

Open scale states a. La gente es/*esta inteligente. The people ser/estar intelligent. ‘People are intelligent.’ b. Las roras son/?estan duras. The rocks ser/estar hard. ‘Rocks are hard.’ c. Las carreteras son/?estan anchas. The roads ser/estar wide. ‘The roads are wide.’

(36)

(Spanish)

Closed scale states a. La gente es/esta feliz. The people ser/estar happy. ‘People are happy.’ b. Las estanques *son/estan vacios. The ponds ser/estar empty. ‘Ponds are empty.’ c. Las cordones ?son/estan rectos. The ropes ser/estar straight. ‘Ropes are straight.’

(Spanish)

Quantifier split in German also yeilds a similar pattern.14 (37)

Open scale states a. * Menschen sind viele intelligent. People are many intelligent. ‘As for people, many are intelligent.’ b. ?? Steine sind viele hart. Rocks are many hard. ‘As for rocks, many are hard.’ c. ?? Strassen sind viele breit. Roads are many wide. ‘As for roads, many are wide.’

(38)

14

(German)

Closed scale states a. ? Menschen sind viele glucklich. People are many happy. ‘As for people, many are happy.’

In German, vollstandig (completely) was used to test for closed scale interpretation of the adjectives.

10

b.

c.

? Seen sind viele leer. Ponds are many empty. ‘As for ponds, many are empty.’ ? Seile sind viele lang. Ropes are many straight. ‘As for ropes, many are straight.’

(German)

This leads us to a very simple relationship between quantity/non-quantity adjectives and stagelevel/individual-level interpretation.15 ,16 (39)

a. If P is quantity, then P is stage-level. b. If P is not quantity, then P is individual-level.

Pulling these pieces together, the following picture emerges. Quantity statives are composed in the same manner as quantity eventives. A quantity internal argument licenses the projection of AspP, which following the universal hierarchy is projected below functional structure which realizes the state/event distinction. 15 Hay et al. (1999); Kennedy and Levin (2002) proposed that scale structure was responsible for telicity of eventive deadjectival verbs.

(1)

a. They are widening the road. (⇒ They have widened the road.) b. They are straightening the rope. (⇒ They have straightened the rope.)

Judgements on this data, however, have been mixed, but consider the following data which receives much clearer judgements from my informants. (2)

a. The workers are widening roads. (⇒ The workers have widened roads.) b. The stylist is straightening hair. (⇒ The stylist has straightened hair.)

(3)

a. The workers are widening the road. (⇒ The workers have widened the road.) b. The stylist is straightening the hair. (⇒ The stylist has straightened the hair.)

As in other cases, the internal argument controls the telicity of the predicate, with non-quantity arguments yeilding atelic readings (2) and quantity arguments yeilding telic readings (3). 16 Certain generalizations about the stage-level/individual-level distinction have made note of the ascribed property as being temporary or permanent (Jager, 2001; Maienborn, 2004; Schmitt, 1992). However, there are “funky facts” about stage-level/individual-level predicates in which our world knowledge about temporary and permanent properties conflicts with the grammar. Consider the following. (1)

a. John was drunk (in the yard/this morning). b. John was dead (in the yard/this morning). c. # John was intelligent (in the yard/this morning).

While drunk can easily be thought of as a temporary property and thus stage-level, dead is not so clear and one might expect it to fall in line with intelligent as a permanent property and thus individual-level. However, note that dead is closed-scale (completely drunk/dead/*intelligent), and by its closed scalar structure, predicates which embed it are interpreted as stage-level.

11

(40)

Composition of Verbal Stative SP λe.own(e)&Int(e, thehouse )&quantity(e, thehouse )&nonatomic(e)

S λe.nonatomic(e)

AspP λe.own(e)&Int(e, thehouse )&quantity(e, empty )

DP the house

(41)

Asp λxλe.own(e)&Int (e, thehouse )&quantity(e, x) (by Var. Id Asp λxλe.quantity(e, x)

VP λe.own(e)&Int(e, thehouse ) V own

tDP

Composition of Deadjectival Quantity Stative17 SP λe.empty(e)&quantity(e, empty )&nonatomic(e)

S λe.nonatomic(e)

AspP λe.empty(e)&quantity(e, empty ) √

Asp λxλe.quantity(e, x)&empty(e) (by Var. Ident.)

P empty

Asp λxλe.quantity(e, x)

t√ P λα.empty (α)

Due to head movement (assuming we still have head movement) or head adjacency (some variant of Fusion in Distributed Morphology) and assuming Late Insertion, we can capture the Spanish copula facts by assuming that [T+S+Asp] is spelled out as estar, whereas [T+S] is spelled-out as ser (Schmitt, 2005).

4

Conclusions

We began with two seemingly seperate questions which I will now give some answers to: • Q: If the stage-level/individual-level distinction is not made in the lexicon, what component (if any) is the distinction based in? A: The stage-level/individual-level distinction is made in the syntax. Functional heads bearing quantity semantics (AspP) compose within the stative to yeild the distinction. Quantity 17

Embick (2004) suggests a similar structure for states on semantic and morphological grounds.

12

statives are interpreted as stage-level while non-quantity statives are interpreted as individuallevel. • Q: How might inner aspect play a role in stative predicates? A: Inner aspect, governed by the projection of AspP, is available in stative predicates. Telicity in eventive predicates is realized by properties of the internal argument’s structure triggering quantity (telic) or non-quantity (atelic) interpretations. The stage-level/individual-level distinction follows the same pattern and is realized by properties of the internal argument’s structure triggering quantity (stage-level) or non-quantity (individual-level) interpretations. And what of variable behavior? I have also assumed throughout that polysemy is a property of sub√ stantive lexical items, or roots (those items which spell-out under P). Given conceptual flexibility, substantive lexical items can be coerced by embedding them in grammatical structure. When the concept indicated by the root is unable to coerce to the structure in which it is embedded, unacceptability arises. Additionally, while polysemy appears pervasive at the level of roots, functional morphemes fail to be polysemeous and form strict interpretations. Thus variable behavior of predicates is to be explained as variable behavior of roots, modulo conceptual complications, yeilding to the structural interpretations in which they are embedded. An open question: • Why are eventives always interpretated as stage-level? In particular, if activities do not project AspP, how are they interpreted as stage-level?

References Bach, Emmon. 1986. The algebra of events. Linguistics and Philosophy 5–16. Borer, Hagit. 2005a. In name only. Structuring Sense. Oxford University Press. Borer, Hagit. 2005b. The normal course of events. Structuring Sense. Oxford University Press. Dowty, David. 1979. Word meanings and montague grammar . Reidel, Dordrecht. Embick, David. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in english. Linguistic Inquiry 355–392. Fernald, Theodore B. 1999. Evidential coercion: Using individual-level predicates in stage-level environments. Studies in the Linguistic Sciences 43–63. Fernald, Theodore B. 2000. Predicates and temporal arguments. Oxford University Press. Fox, Danny, and Martin Hackl. 2006. The universal density of measurement. Linguistics and Philosophy 537–586. Harley, Heidi, and Rolf Noyer. 1999. State-of-the-article: Distributed morphology. Glot International 3–9. Hay, Jennifer, Christopher Kennedy, and Beth Levin. 1999. Scalar structure underlies telicity in “degree achievements”. In Salt ix , ed. T Matthews and D Strolovitch, 127–144. CLC Publications.

13

Jager, Gerhard. 2001. Topic-comment structure and the contrast between stage level and individual level predicates. Journal of Semantics 83–126. Kennedy, Chris, and Beth Levin. 2002. Telicity corresponds to degree of change. In Topics in the Grammar of Scalar Expressions. UCLA. Kennedy, Christopher. 1997. Projection the adjective: The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison. Doctoral Dissertation, University of California, Santa Cruz. Kennedy, Christopher. 2001. Polar opposition and the ontology of ’degrees’. Linguistics and Philosophy 33–70. Kennedy, Christopher, and Louise McNally. 2005. Scale structure, degree modification, and the semantics of gradable predicates. Language 345–381. Kratzer, Angelica. 1995. Stage-level/individual-level predicates. In The generic book , ed. G.N. Carlson and F.J. Pelletier, 125–175. University of Chicago Press. Kratzer, Angelica. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Phrase structure and the lexicon, ed. J. Rooryck and Laurie Zaring, 109–137. Dordrecht, Kluwer. Maienborn, Claudia. 2004. A pragmatic explanation of the stage level/individual level contrast in combination with locatives. In Proceedings of the western conference on linguistics, ed. Brian Agbayani, Vida Samiian, and Benjamin Tucker, 158–179. Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. In Proceedings of the 21st annual penn linguistics colloquium, ed. Alexis Dimitriadis et al., 201–225. Rosen, Sara Thomas. 1999. State-of-the-article: The syntactic representation of linguistic events. Glot International 3–10. Schmitt, Christina J. 1996. Aspect and the syntax of noun phrases. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Maryland. Schmitt, Cristina. 1992. Ser and Estar : A matter of aspect. In Proceesings of NELS , 411–425. Schmitt, Cristina. 2005. Semi-copulas: Event and aspectual composition. In Aspectual inquiries, ed. P. Kempchinsky and R. Slabakova, 121–145. Kluwer. Verkuyl, Henk J. 1972. The compositional nature of the aspects. Foundations of Language Supplementary Series. D. Reidel Publishing Company. Verkuyl, Henk J. 1993. Aspectual issues: Studies on time and quantity. Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.

14

Stative Quantity

Voice λxλe.sneeze(e)&V oice(e, x) (by Event Ident.) Voice λxλe.V oice(e, x) ..... pretation a stative receives to the extent that they are closed or open scale. Quantity adjectives ..... In Proceedings of the western conference on linguistics, ed. Brian.

169KB Sizes 2 Downloads 182 Views

Recommend Documents

Academia's obsession with quantity
However, a bigger group of researchers does not necessarily produce ... Creativity greatly benefits from an environment that is supportive, collaborative ... analysis of the funding of the top 1% most highly cited ecologists. Oikos. 121, 1005– ...

COMPLETE LIST OF STATIVE VERBS.pdf
Whoops! There was a problem loading more pages. Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. COMPLETE LIST OF STATIVE VERBS.pdf. COMPLETE LIST OF

COMPLETE LIST OF STATIVE VERBS.pdf
... many movies, most of them were actually very good. 9. I don't know for sure who stole the money, but I ...........................it was Jenna. 10. How could you sell my ...

Autodesk Quantity Takeoff.pdf
http://www.linkedin.com/in/omarslm. ر م. ص و. )ر ( ال bim. ت ا. ، ا-وم 9س (رق ال 5رت ( ل ام طء. ورت دا. و رة و. ل ا5ل ا. ء ال و ا. 5ء ال. FAMILIES و TEMPLATES. ب : MAGICAD & SKETCH UP& GREEN. BUILDING &

Quantity Freeze Limits for Indices - NSE
Feb 28, 2018 - ... file available on extranet path faoftp/faocommon before trading on March 01, 2018. Details of quantity freeze in respect of each underlying shall be available on the website. For and on behalf of. National Stock Exchange of India L

Combinatorial and Quantity-Discount Procurement ...
IBM T.J. Watson Research Center, PO Box 218, Yorktown Heights, New York 10598 ... 24. Vol. 33, No. 1, January–February 2003 calls its employees associates and spreads responsibil ...... drop from one hour for first-time users to less than 10.

Quantity Food Production Techniques.PDF
preparation. 10. Write note on : (a) Marzipan. (b) Biscuits. (c) Sugar. BHY-032 2. Page 2 of 2. Main menu. Displaying Quantity Food Production Techniques.PDF.

511 Grammar Present Simple vs Present Progresive, Stative verbs ...
511 Grammar Present Simple vs Present Progresive, Stative verbs (hub 3A).pdf. 511 Grammar Present Simple vs Present Progresive, Stative verbs (hub 3A).pdf.

PDF Construction Quantity Surveying
A Dictionary of Construction, Surveying, and Civil Engineering (Oxford Quick Reference) · Construction Project Manager's Pocket Book (Routledge Pocket Books).

CE6704-Estimation and Quantity Surveying.pdf
9 Briefly explain various types of estimates in detail? BT-3. Page 3 of 12. CE6704-Estimation and Quantity Surveying.pdf. CE6704-Estimation and Quantity ...

Math quantity activity sheets.pdf
Page 1 of 6. 1 2. Page 1 of 6. Page 2 of 6. 3 4. Page 2 of 6. Page 3 of 6. 5 6. Page 3 of 6. Page 4 of 6. 7 8. Page 4 of 6. Math quantity activity sheets.pdf.

ii semester examinations, april/may, 2011 estimating quantity survey ...
PART – B (48 Marks) · 4. Figure.1 shows the plan and sectional details of a two roomed building. Estimate · the quantities of the following items. i) Earthwork in Excavation in foundation · ii) Lime Concrete in foundation · iii) I · st · Class Bric

Civil At Work_ How To Calculate Staircase Concrete Quantity _.pdf ...
Civil At Work_ How To Calculate Staircase Concrete Quantity _.pdf. Civil At Work_ How To Calculate Staircase Concrete Quantity _.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with.

Role of hydrodynamic conditions on quantity and ... - Springer Link
diately after recovery, samples were vertically sliced into five ... Data were normalised to sediment dry weight. ..... Lowry, O. H. & N. J. Rosebrough, 1951. Protein ...

PDF Download Quantity Surveying Practice Full Books
Practice and Procedure for the Quantity Surveyor · Willis's Elements of Quantity Surveying · Construction Project Manager's Pocket Book (Routledge Pocket ...

Testing the Quantity-Quality Trade-Off in India
Using data from a representative sample from India, we test the empirical validity of ... 2India's adult illiteracy levels are a big concern, which stands at 39%. ..... missing or unreliable information on any of the variables used in the analysis.