Stable Coalition-Governments under Weighted Political Agreements M. Socorro Puy Dpto. Teoría e Historia Económica Universidad de Málaga, Spain. March 26, 2009

Abstract Once elections have taken place, we consider that three parties can hold o¢ ce in the form of two-party coalitions. Political parties are both: o¢ ce seeking and policy motivated. Each coalition should reach an agreement concerning their political position. We explore whether there are …xed negotiation rules as well as simple mechanisms that guarantee that parties can form stable coalition-governments. First, we de…ne a family of rules, the Weighted Rules, that select agreements as a function of the parties’ bliss points and electoral results (Gamson’s Law, or equal share among others qualify as weighted rules). We then show that every weighted rule yields a unique stable coalition. Second, we prove that there is no mechanism which dominant-strategies equilibrium outcomes always select the stable coalition. We then propose a simple mechanism which Nash and strong-Nash equilibrium outcomes coincide with the stable coalition. Keywords: Government-coalition, Stability, Mechanism, Nashimplementation. Jels: D71, D72. The author thanks Pablo Amorós, Carmen Beviá, Francis Bloch, Luis Corchón, Dinko Dimitrov and Miguel Angel Meléndez for their helpful comments. Financial assistance from Ministerio de Ciencia e Innovación under the project SECO2008-03674/ECON, and Junta de Andalucía under the project SEJ1645 is gratefully acknowledged.

1

1

Introduction

When no political party reaches a strict majority in the elections, coalition governments should be formed. Political parties are the main actors in the bargaining process that leads to government formation. As shown by the empirical works of Diermeier et al. (2003), Müller and Str;m (2000), coalition governments are the norm in many European governments. When a coalition of political parties governs, stability of such government is one of the voters’main concerns. In brief, stability requires that no (majoritarian) coalition has incentives to interfere the governing coalition. In this paper, we explore whether there are …xed negotiation rules as well as simple mechanisms (set of rules or protocols) that guarantee that after the elections parties can come up with a stable coalition-government. As far as we know, we provide the …rst contribution where Implementation Theory is applied to solve the coalition-government problem.1 We analyze the case where three parties can hold o¢ ce in the form of two-party coalitions.2 Each party is identi…ed with a bliss-point in a multidimensional policy space. Elections have already taken place. We assume that when forming coalition-governments, parties are not only policy-motivated, but they also derive some bene…ts from holding o¢ ce. The policy adopted by a coalition is an agreement (or pact). Each agreement describes the policy that a coalition intends to pursue if it governs. Under majority rule and a multidimensional policy space, no coalition can propose a policy that majority defeats every other policy (see Scho…eld, 1983; and Saari, 1997 for a formal proof of this statement). This observation was made by Plott (1967), who also suggested that there are some restrictions or constraints on the policies that a coalition can propose. Following Plott, if we account for the rule under which coalitions operate, it can be shown that there exist agreements that cannot be majority defeated. In this paper, we propose some …xed negotiation rules under which coalitions can operate: the Weighted Rules. First, we de…ne the weighted functions that distribute bargaining power among parties as a function of their 1

The pioneering reference in Implementation Theory is due to Maskin (1977). The empirical evidence on Western Europe governments analyzed in Müller and Str;m (2000) provides several examples within our scope (Germany and Luxemburg among others, where a three-party system and a two-party coalition government has been the norm during most of the time). As show by Aragonès (2007b), this scenario also represents the two last Catalan’elections. 2

2

electoral results. We account for a diverse distribution of bargaining power: from equal-share to proportional share. Second, we de…ne the weighted rules that select agreements as a function of parties’bargaining powers and ideal political positions. The agreements derived in this way are a weighted average of the parties’political positions. Our main result is that every weighted rule yields a unique stable coalition (the agreement of this coalition cannot be majority defeated by the agreements of other coalitions). For each weighted rule, the stable function selects the only coalition that is stable. We then study the existence of mechanisms implementing the stable function. A mechanism speci…es a space of messages (one for each party), and an outcome function (once each party announces a message, the outcome function selects a coalition).3 We show that there is no mechanism implementing the stable function in dominant strategies. Then, we analyze implementation in Nash equilibrium. We explore simple mechanisms where parties’messages are simultaneous (in this way we avoid a rule of order with the formateur as a player with …rst-move advantage). We study the simultaneous-unanimity mechanism where each party simultaneously announces a coalition that shall include itself.4 If two parties announce the same coalition, the outcome function selects such coalition. We show that this mechanism fails at implementing the stable function in Nash equilibrium. We then analyze an extended version of this mechanism where parties can announce any coalition (it only adds an extra element to each party’s message space). We show that the proposed mechanism implements in Nash and strong Nash equilibrium the stable function. Furthermore, we show that every equilibrium of this mechanism (Nash and strong Nash) has a natural interpretation since the two parties that form the stable coalition announce such coalition. There are two related papers (Kirchsteiger and Puppe, 1997 and Aragonès, 2007a) that analyze coalition formation governments when parties’incentives are twofold: o¢ ce-seeking, and policy-motivated. None of these authors, however, have suggested a concrete bargaining procedure, neither have they aimed at proposing coalition-formation mechanisms. Kirchsteiger and Puppe (1997) propose two di¤erent models. Their second model is closely related to ours. The policy-motivated incentives, as 3 As pointed out by Jackson (2001), once the preferences of the individuals are speci…ed, the mechanism induces a game. 4 The name of this game is due to von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944, section 57.3.1 ). See also Yi (2003) for a survey on games of coalition formation.

3

introduced by these authors, are based on the distant between the parties’ political positions. Their assumption is not very standard since, as they claim, they do not account for the parties bargaining process. We show that the preferences of the parties, as represented by these authors, can be implicitly deduced when parties’agreements are made according to a weighted rule. Aragonès (2007a) proposes a two-dimensional policy space where four political parties have symmetric political positions. She assumes that parties do not accept those political agreements from which the party’bene…ts are below its reservation value. She characterizes the stable government con…gurations (coalitions and political agreements) in terms of the parties’ reservation values and preferences’intensity over the issues. The present paper is also related to the literature on legislative bargaining games. While we propose …xed negotiation rules, this literature provides predictions on the governing coalitions and legislative voting positions as a result of the parties’bargaining process (see for instance Baron and Ferejohn, 1989; Baron, 1991; Jackson and Moselle, 2002; and Banks and Duggan, 2006).5 The rest of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 describes the model. Section 3 de…nes the weighted rules and derives the results on stability. Section 4 presents the results on implementation. Section 5 concludes.

2

The model

There are three political parties N = f1; 2; 3g : Let RM be the policy space where M 2 is the number of political issues. Each party i 2 N has a di¤erent bliss-point xi 2 RM which speci…es its ideal policy on each of the political issues. Elections have already taken place. Each party’s number of votes (or seats in parliament) are given by = ( 1 ; 2 ; 3 ) where i > 0 for every i 2 N . A strict majority of votes is required to govern. No single party has a strict majority, but every two-party coalition is a winning coalition. We consider that the three-party coalition is implausible. Every (winning) coalition is denoted by S; where S 2 ff1,2g , f1,3g , f2,3gg. An agreement for coalition S is given by xS 2 RM ; it speci…es the policy that 5

If parties’preferences over policies are discounted over time, agreements that are not majority defeated can be achieved at some point of the parties’bargaining procedure.

4

coalition S will support if it governs. A pro…le of agreements x describes an agreement for each coalition, x = (x12 ; x13 ; x23 ). Preferences of party i over agreements are represented by ui (xS ) =

ki

xS xi when i 2 S xS xi when i 2 =S

(1)

where ki > 0 is party i’s bene…ts from holding o¢ ce, and k:k is the euclidean distance between coalition S’s agreement and party i’s bliss-point.6 We take ki su¢ ciently large as to guarantee that each party’s most preferred agreement is one where it is included.7 0 Given two di¤erent agreements xS ; xS ; we say that party i strictly prefers 0 coalition S to coalition S 0 when ui (xS ) > ui (xS ) (when convenient we use notation S i S 0 ). Each pro…le of agreements x, induces a pro…le of parties’ preferences over coalitions = ( 1 ; 2 ; 3 ), where each i speci…es party i’s preferences over the three coalitions. For the sake of simplicity we do not consider indi¤erences.8 We say that xS is e¢ cient when there is no x0 2 RM such that ui (x0 ) > ui (xS ) for all i 2 S: Thus, if xS is e¢ cient, the parties included in coalition S cannot improve simultaneously by choosing another agreement. Every e¢ cient agreement is located in the line between the two parties’bliss points. A pro…le of agreements x is e¢ cient if every agreement in x is e¢ cient. De…nition: Given a pro…le of agreements x and its induced preferences over coalitions , we say that coalition S is stable if it does not exist another coalition S 0 such that S 0 i S for all i 2 S 0 :

When S is stable, there is no other coalition S 0 which members strictly 0 improve with their agreement xS respect to xS : If S is stable, we say that S cannot be blocked by any other coalition. A pro…le of agreements x is stable if there is some coalition S that is stable. If x is not stable, every coalition is blocked by another coalition. In this case, the induced preferences over coalitions contain one of the following two 6

Rijt (2008) proposes an alternative representation of policy-motivated incentives where parties’objective consists of achieving a desirable policy on as many issues as possible. 7 Our proposal is not within the scope of hedonic coalition structures (see Banerjee, Konishi and Sönmez 2001 and Bogomolnaia and Jackson 2002) since preferences over those coalitions where a party is not included, depend on the agreement made by the other parties. On this point we di¤er from Aragonès (2007a), Kirchsteiger and Puppe (1997), but we coincide with Rijt (2008). 8 Note that this is a minor assumption in a multidimensional policy space.

5

circles: f1; 2g 1 f1; 3g 3 f2; 3g 2 f1; 2g, or f1; 3g 1 f1; 2g 2 f2; 3g 3 f1; 3g, i.e., if for instance party 1 prefers party 2 as a partner (better than 3), then party 2 prefers party 3 (better than 1), and party 3 prefers party 1 (better than 2).9

3

The weighted rules

In this section we propose a family of rules that select pro…les of agreements as a function of parties’number of votes and parties’bliss points. The negotiation of agreements within coalitions can be made according to di¤erent bargaining weights. Several authors analyze bargaining rules from a theoretical, empirical, and experimental point of view. For instance, Carrol and Cox (2007) provide an empirical analysis that supports Gamson’s Law (each party bargaining power is proportional to the party’s contribution of seats to the coalition) as the criterion that parties follow when coalition-pacts are pre-electoral. As shown in the experiments proposed by Fréchette et al. (2005), post-electoral pacts are however characterized by other distributions of bargaining power such as the ability to form majoritarian coalitions. As we next show, our proposal of weighted rules de…nes a family of rules su¢ ciently extensive as to include di¤erent procedures that determine bargaining powers. A weighted function distributes bargaining power among political parties. Formally, the weighted function f assigns to each party’ P s number of votes (or seats), a fraction of power f ( i ) > 0 such that f ( i ) = 1. Particular i2N

instances of weighted functions are the proportional function f ( i ) =

Pi

i

,

i2N

the equal-share function f ( i ) = 31 (it represents a "pivotalness measure" since every party is crucial in the same number of winning coalitions), as well as every convex combination of these two functions among others. Each weighted function de…nes a di¤erent weighted rule: De…nition: The weighted rule Wf associated to a weighted function f selects, for each distribution of votes and parties’ bliss points, a pro…le of 9

There are however examples of preferences containing circles and where there is a stable coalition.

6

13 23 S agreements, Wf ( ; x1 ; x2 ; x3 ) = (x12 f ; xf ; xf ); where each xf satis…es:

P

f ( i )xi xSf = P : f ( i) i2S

(2)

i2S

Thus, each xSf is a weighted average of the bliss points of the parties included in S: We refer to every xSf as a weighted agreement. To provide some examples, if f is the proportional function, then xSf = P

ix

i2S

P

i

i

; i.e., the weighted rule yields agreements according to Gamson’s Law.10

i2S

If f is the equal share function, then every agreement selected the weighted P by xi rule is the midpoint of the parties’bliss-points, i.e., xSf = . 2 i2S

Let S = fi; jg ; substituting Expression (2) in the utility function of party i yields f ( i )xi +f ( j )xj xi ; ui (xSf ) = ki f ( i )+f ( j ) and simplifying ui (xSf ) = ki

f(

f( j) i )+f (

j)

xj

xi :

(3)

Hence, when agreements are selected according to a weighted rule, parties’preferences over those coalitions where they are included, depend on the distant between the parties’bliss points.11 Appendix A shows that Expression 3 can be also derived from the Generalized Nash Bargaining solution of a bargaining game within the parties in the coalition. The following example illustrates a weighted rule. 10

This is in fact the norm in two-party races that operate under proportional representation (see for instance Austen-Smith and Banks, 1988; Grossman and Helpman, 1996). In a one-dimensional policy space Le Breton et al. (2008) show that Gamson’s Law yields a stable coalition, here we generalize this particular result. 11 Preferences over coalitions as proposed by Kirchsteiger and Puppe (1997) are ui (S) =

g(

j i+

j

d(xj ; xi )) if i 2 S 0 if i 2 =S

where d is a distant function, and g is strictly decreasing in d. These authors claim that, in their proposal, there is no explicit speci…cation of the actual outcome of the bargaining process. We however show that their preferences intrinsically specify a procedure to select agreements.

7

Example 1: Consider the parties’ bliss-points as represented in Figure 1. The weighted function is such that f ( 1 ) = f ( 2 ) = :25; f ( 3 ) = :5. The pro…le of agreements selected by the weighted rule are represented as follows:

x2

xf12 xf23 x3

x1 xf13

Figure 1: A pro…le of weighted agreements

Note that the lines from the bliss points to the agreements of the opposite side must cross in a single point (the weighted baricenter). We can derive the induced preferences over coalitions (ordered from top to bottom): Party 1 Party 2 Party 3 12 12 23 13 23 13 23 13 12 In this example, coalition S = f1,2g is stable (the two other coalitions are blocked by f1,2g). The weighted rules yield e¢ cient pro…les of agreements, i.e., every weighted agreement is e¢ cient. If a weighted rule yields stable pro…les of agreements, then at least one of the coalitions must be stable. This is in fact the case as we next show. Theorem 1 Every weighted rule Wf yields stable pro…les of agreements. Proof. Suppose to the contrary that there is a pro…le of agreements selected by a weighted rule that is not stable. Then, preferences over coalitions must

8

contain a circle. Consider without loss of generality that f1; 2g f2; 3g 2 f1; 2g. Then, by Expression (3): f1; 2g f2; 3g f1; 3g

1 2 3

f1; 3g implies kx1 f1; 2g implies kx2 f2; 3g implies kx1

From (a), kx1

kx2

x2 k < kx1

( 3) x3 k f ( 2f)+f ( 2 3

3)

< kx1

f ( 2) f ( 2 )+f (

x2 k f ( x3 k f ( x3 k f ( x3 k ff (( x3 k

f( f( 1

f(

2)

1 )+f ( 2 ) f ( 3) 2 )+f ( 3 ) f ( 1) 1 )+f ( 3 )

< kx1 < kx1 < kx2

3 )(f ( 1 )+f ( 2 )) 2 )(f ( 1 )+f ( 3 )) 3 )(f ( 1 )+f ( 2 ))

x3 k f ( x2 k f ( x3 k f (

f(

1

f1; 3g

3)

1 )+f ( 3 ) f ( 1) 1 )+f ( 2 ) f ( 2) 2 )+f ( 3 )

:

3

(a) (b) (c)

: Substituting it in (b), f(

1)

2 )(f ( 1 )+f ( 3 )) f ( 1 )+f ( 2 ) f ( 1) 3

; that simplifying

yields, kx xk < kx x k f ( 1 )+f ( 3 ) ; which contradicts (c). 3) Therefore, preferences do not contain a circle, and so, there is at least a coalition that is stable.12 As a consequence of Theorem 1, we can derive the following result.

13 23 Corollary 1: Given a pro…le of weighted agreements (x12 f ; xf ; xf ), there is a unique stable coalition. Furthermore, if S is stable, then coalition S must be top-ranked for both parties in S and bottom-ranked for the remaining party.

Proof. Suppose without loss of generality that f1; 3g is stable. By Theorem 1, every pro…le of agreements selected by a weighted rule is such that preferences over coalitions do not contain a circle. Three cases are possible. Case 1: f1; 3g 1 f1; 2g and f1; 3g 3 f2; 3g : It implies that f1; 3g is stable. Since nor f2; 3g can be top-ranked for party 1, neither f1; 2g can be topranked for party 3, then f1; 3g must be top-ranked for party 1 and party 3. 23 Besides, by e¢ ciency of x12 f and xf ; coalition f1; 3g must be bottom-ranked for party 2. Case 2: f1; 2g 1 f1; 3g and f1; 2g 2 f2; 3g : Then, to guarantee that f1; 3g is stable, f1; 3g must be top ranked for party 2, a contradiction. Case 3: f2; 3g 2 f1; 2g and f2; 3g 3 f1; 3g : Then, to guarantee that f1; 3g is stable, f1; 3g must be top-ranked for party 2, a contradiction. Finally, suppose that there are two stable coalitions S and S 0 . Then, both coalitions must be top-ranked for the party in the intersection S \ S 0 ; but it contradicts the fact that there are no indi¤erences. We next describe all the pro…les of preferences over (winning) coalitions where f1; 3g is stable (changing the identity of the parties we can derive every 12

For this proof, we only need parties’preference ordering on those coalitions where it is included. Thus, the proof basically follows the lines of Kirchsteiger and Puppe (1997) (p. 20).

9

possible pro…le of preferences). 1 2 3 13 12 13 12 23 23 23 13 12

1 2 3 13 23 13 12 12 23 23 13 12

1 2 3 13 23 13 12 12 12 23 13 23

1 2 3 13 12 13 23 23 23 12 13 12

When describing these pro…les, we do not only account for the results in Corollary 1, but also for the fact that every agreement is e¢ cient. Thus, if f1; 2g 2 f2; 3g then by e¢ ciency of the weighted agreement x23 f , party 3’s preferences cannot be such that f1; 2g 3 f2; 3g : The weighted rules de…ne a restricted domain of preferences over coalitions. In view of the above results, there are up to twelve di¤erent pro…les of preferences over coalitions that can be induced by the weighted rules.

4

Implementing the stable function

When each party not only knows its preferences over coalitions, but also the preferences of the other two parties, they may easily come up with the stable coalition.13 In this case, those parties that are members of the stable coalition will not accept any other partner to govern, but the one of its top-ranked coalition. However, if parties do not know each other preferences, there is no reason to expect that the stable coalition will govern. In this case, a party may have incentives to accept forming government with another party even when it is not its top-ranked option. In this section we aim at exploring mechanisms that guarantee that, after the elections, parties can form stable coalition-governments even when parties do not know its partners’preferences.14 The weighted rules induce a restricted domain of preferences that we denote by R. We perform as a central planner who knows the set of admissible pro…les of preferences over coalitions (the domain R), but ignores the particular realization of such pro…le. Some previous de…nitions are required. 13

Even when they do not know that our goal is achieving a stable coalition. Parties may not even know the domain of preferences. Thus, we consider privacypreserving mechanism as de…ned by Hurwicz (1972), since we do not account for the information that a party has on its partner’s preferences. In this way, we cover every possible scenario where parties have a piece of information. 14

10

The Stable Function S selects, for each admissible pro…le of preferences over coalitions 2 R, the stable coalition. Thus, S( ) 2 ff1,2g , f1,3g , f2,3gg. A mechanism is a pair (M; g) where M = Mi ; each Mi is the message i2N

space for party i; and g is the outcome function that assigns to each pro…le of messages, a coalition. Thus, for each m 2 M; g(m) 2 ff1; 2g , f1; 3g , f2; 3gg is the resulting outcome. An equilibrium concept speci…es the strategic behavior of individuals faced with mechanism (M; g): We use the notions of dominant strategies, Nash equilibrium, and strong Nash equilibrium as equilibrium concepts.15 A coalition generated as the outcome of an equilibrium of the mechanism (M; g) is called equilibrium coalition and is denoted by E(M; g; ). De…nition: The mechanism (M; g) implements the Stable Function S via an equilibrium concept when every equilibrium coalition is a stable coalition, i.e., E(M; g; ) = S( ) for every 2 R:

When a mechanism implements the Stable Function, in every realization of the parties’ preferences over coalitions, the resulting outcome obtained through strategic behavior (on the part of the parties facing the mechanism) is a stable coalition.16 When a mechanism implements via two di¤erent equilibrium concepts, we refer to double-implementation. We …rst show that there is no mechanism implementing the Stable Function in dominant strategies. Theorem 2 The Stable Function is not implementable in dominant strategies. Proof. According to Corollary 1, the domain of preferences R does not have a Cartesian product structure. Therefore, the standard revelation principle cannot be applied here.17 15

The strong-Nash equilibrium is a Nash equilibrium where no coalition can improve deviating. 16 Bloch (1996) shows, in a setting of coalition formation with externalities, that any core stable structure can be obtained as the equilibrium outcome of a sequential coalition formation game. Implementation of the core requires, additionally, that every equilibrium outcome of the game be a core stable structure (see Serrano 1995; Serrano and Vohra 1997). 17 See also Amorós et al. (2002) for another restricted domain that has a non-cartisan product structure, and where the proposed social choice function is not implementable in dominant strategies.

11

Each party i has four types of preference relations denoted by f 1i ; Consider the following three admissible pro…les of preferences: (

1 1,

1 2,

1 3)

1 2 3 13 12 13 12 23 23 23 13 12

(

2 1,

1 2,

2 3)

(

1 2 3 12 12 23 13 23 13 23 13 12

1 1,

2 2,

2 i;

3 i;

4 ig:

2 3)

1 2 3 13 23 23 12 12 13 23 13 12

If we suppose that there exists a mechanism (M; g) implementing S in dominant strategies, then each party i should have a dominant strategy for each type of preferences. Let m1i be the dominant strategy for party i when party i’s preferences are 1i , then according to the above described preferences, the outcome function g should satisfy: g(m11 ; m12 ; m13 ) = f1; 3g g(m21 ; m12 ; m23 ) = f1; 2g g(m11 ; m22 ; m23 ) = f2; 3g :

(4)

However, if we consider the following non admissible pro…le of preferences18 : (

1 1,

1 2,

2 3)

1 2 3 13 12 23 12 23 13 23 13 12 where there is no stable coalition, the outcome function can select any coalition g(m11 ; m12 ; m23 ) 2 S: Suppose that g(m11 ; m12 ; m23 ) = f1; 2g ; then given the preference relations of party 3, this party improves deviating to m13 since then, as speci…ed by (4), the outcome is f1; 3g and it contradicts that m23 is a dominant strategy for party 3 when its preferences are 23 . Suppose that g(m11 ; m12 ; m23 ) = f1; 3g ; then given the preferences of party 2, this party improves deviating to m22 since then, as speci…ed in (4), the outcome is f2; 3g ant it contradicts that m12 is a dominant strategy for party 2 when its preferences are 12 . Suppose that g(m11 ; m12 ; m23 ) = f2; 3g ; then given the preferences of party 1, this party improves deviating to m21 since then, as speci…ed in (4), 18

Here we consider that parties do not know the domain of preferences.

12

the outcome is f1; 2g ant it contradicts that m11 is a dominant strategy for party 1 when its preferences are 11 . It proves that no party has a dominant strategy, which contradicts that the stable function is implementable in dominant strategies. The direct mechanism is the general canonical mechanism where the message space of each party contains its pro…les of preferences over coalitions, and the outcome function selects the stable coalition from the announced pro…les of preferences. We …nd that the direct mechanism fails in our setting since, it is not a dominant strategy for each party to truthfully reveal its preferences. Furthermore, there is no other mechanism implementing in dominant strategies the stable function. We therefore, consider implementation in Nash equilibrium. We aim at proposing simple and natural mechanisms implementing in Nash equilibrium.19 We analyze two di¤erent mechanisms where players simultaneously announce their messages (see Figure 2 and Figure 3). Our …rst mechanism is the simultaneous-unanimity mechanism. Each party simultaneously announces a coalition that includes himself, i.e., Mi = ffi; jg ; fi; kgg for all i 2 N: The outcome function is such that if two parties announce the same coalition, such coalition is formed. If every two parties announce a di¤erent coalition there is a lottery, denoted by L; that assigns equal probability to the three possible coalitions.20 1 12

13

2 12

23

12

23

3 13

12

23 13

12

L

23

13

23

13

23

23

13

L

13

23

Figure 2: Simultaneous-unanimity mechanism 19

A simple mechanism refers to a reduced message space. Natural refers to the interpretation of such mechanism in relation to the context where it is applied. 20 Preferences are measured according to von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions.

13

The messages where each party announces its top-ranked coalition are Nash equilibrium. We …nd, however, that the proposed mechanism has Nash equilibria which do not yield stable coalitions. Consider, for instance, the following pro…le of preferences where f1; 2g is stable: 1 2 3 12 12 23 13 23 13 23 13 12 The pro…le of messages (m1 ; m2 ; m3 ) = (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) is a Nash equilibrium where g(m) = f2; 3g (if party 2 deviates, the outcome function selects the lottery that may not improve party 2). Thus, we conclude that the proposed mechanism fails at implementing the stable function in Nash equilibrium (even if instead of L; the outcome is a concrete coalition).21 Next, we aim at …nding the minimal extension of the previous mechanism that guarantees Nash-implementation. We enlarge each party’s message space with an additional message so that Mi = ff1; 2g , f1; 3g , f2; 3gg for all i 2 N . As in the previous mechanism, each party simultaneously announces a message. We call this proposal the enlarged-simultaneous-unanimity mechanism. There are basically two rules that describe the outcome function. Rule 1: if two parties fi; jg announce the same coalition S = fi; jg ; then the outcome function proposes coalition S (the case where the three parties announce the same coalition is included in this rule). Rule 2: if two parties fi; jg announce the same coalition S 6= fi; jg and the third party announces another coalition S 0 , the outcome function g selects the coalition that is complement to the party in the intersection, i.e., g(m) = N nS \ S 0 . There are two exceptions to this rule: when party 1 and party 2 announce S = f2; 3g ; then g(m) = m3 ; and when party 2 and party 3 announce S = f1; 2g then g(m) = m1 (in both exceptions, the outcome function selects the coalition announced by the third party). Finally, the mechanism preserves anonymity in the sense that every party has the same message space, and each party (or coalition) is selected by the outcome function the same number of times. 21 It can be shown that the simultaneous-unanimity mechanism implements the stable function in strong-Nash equilibrium and coalition-proof Nash equilibrium (see Bernheim et al. 1987 for a de…nition of the later equilibrium concept).

14

1 13

12

23

2 13

12

12

23

13

12

23

13

23

3 12 12

13 23 12

12

12 23

13 23 12 23

13 13

13 23 12

23

12

13 23

13 13

12

23 23

13 23 12 13

12 12

13 23 12 13

23 23

13 23 23

12

13 13

13 23 12

12

12 12

13 23

13

23

Figure 3: Enlarged-simultaneous-unanimity mechanism

The outcome function is designed so that in every Nash equilibrium, those parties that form the stable coalition do announce such coalition (whatever the message of the third party). Thus, for every other pro…le of messages, at least one of the political parties improves deviating. Theorem 3 The enlarged-simultaneous-unanimity mechanism double implements the Stable function in Nash and strong-Nash equilibrium. Proof. (See Appendix B). The proposed mechanism is immune to deviations of coalitions since every Nash equilibrium of the game is also strong-Nash equilibrium.

5

Final Remarks

Our analysis leaves several open lines for future research. We have studied the scenario where there are three parties and every two-party is a winning coalition. If we move to other scenarios, stability cannot be granted, unless other considerations (such as ideological-incompatibility, or pre-electoral coalitions among others) be taken into account. Finally, we can think on agreements made not only on policies, but also on cabinet portfolios. We conjecture that it can be included without modifying, in a substantial way, the main results.

15

APPENDIX Appendix A: The weighted rule and the Generalized Nash Bargaining Solution22 We next show that the utility that the parties in S = fi; jg derive from a weighted agreement xSf coincides with the utility derived from the twoagents Generalized Nash Bargaining Solution of the game with bargaining set f(vi ; vj ) : vi + vj kxi xj kg ; disagreement point (ui (xj ); uj (xi )); and agents’weights f ( i ); f ( j ). The generalized Nash Bargaining solution to two-person bargaining problems f( ) f( ) is de…ned by maximizing over the bargaining set the product vi i vj j = K. Solving this problem, the slope of the bargaining set is tangent to the slope 1 v f( ) f ( i) . Thus, in the bargaining solution we have vi f ( ji ) = 1 of vi = ( fK ( j) ) vj

j

and since vi + vj = kx f(

)

i

j

x k ; we deduce that vi = kx

i

j

x k f(

f(

i)

i )+f ( j )

,

vj = kxi xj k f ( i )+fj ( j ) : Each party utility in the disagreement point is given by ui (xj ) = ki kxj xi k and uj (xi ) = kj kxi xj k : Thus, each party utility in the bargaining solution is ui = ui (xj )+vi and uj = uj (xi )+vj , f( j) where substituting the values vi ; vj yields ui = ki kxi xj k ; f ( i )+f ( j ) u j = kj

f(

f(

i)

i )+f ( j )

kxi

xj k (which coincides with Expression 3).

Appendix B: Proof of Theorem 3: Proof. First, we show that S( ) 2 E(M; g; ) for any 2 R: Given some 2 R; consider that S( ) = f1; 3g. Then by Corollary 1, f1; 3g is top ranked for party 1 and party 3. Let m = (f1; 3g ; m2 ; f1; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 3g for all m2 2 M2 : Nor party 1, neither party 3 have incentives to deviate, and party 2 cannot modify the outcome. Thus, m is a Nash equilibrium and so, f1; 3g 2 E(m; g; ): The same reasoning applies when either S( ) = f1; 2g or S( ) = f2; 3g : Second, we show that E(M; g; ) 2 S( ) for any 2 R: Consider the following Nash equilibria: Let m = (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; m3 ) where m3 2 M3 ; then g(m) = f1; 2g : By Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g 1 f1; 3g and f1; 2g 2 f2; 3g : Thus, f1; 2g is top ranked for party 1 and party 2, which implies that f1; 2g is stable. Let m = (f1; 3g ; m2 ; f1; 3g) where m2 2 M2 ; then g(m) = f1; 3g : By Nash 22

See Harsanyi and Selten (1972).

16

equilibrium, f1; 3g 1 f1; 2g and f1; 3g 2 f2; 3g : Thus, f1; 3g is top ranked for party 1 and party 3, which implies thatf1; 3g is stable. Let m = (m1 ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) where m1 2 M1 ; then g(m) = f2; 3g : By Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g 2 f1; 2g and f2; 3g 3 f1; 3g : Thus, f2; 3g is top ranked for party 2 and party 3, which implies that f2; 3g is stable. Third, we show that the proposed mechanism has no other Nash equilibrium. Let m = (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g where g(m) = f2; 3g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g and g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1, coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. Then, party 1 improves deviating since g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) where g(m) = f2; 3g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 2g and g (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 can improve deviating since g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) where g(m) = f2; 3g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 2g and g (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 improves deviating since g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 2g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f1; 3g : Since g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g and g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 3g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 2. In such case, party 2 improves deviating since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 2g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 2g : Since g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g and g (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 2. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 2g has to be bottom ranked for party 3. In such case, party 3 improves deviating since g (f1; 2g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f1; 3g : Since 17

g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g and g (f1; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 3g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 2. In such case, party 2 improves deviating since g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) where g(m) = f2; 3g : Since g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 2g and g (f1; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 improves deviating since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 2g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f2; 3g : Since g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g and g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 improves deviating since g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 2g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 3g and g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 2. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 2g has to be bottom ranked for party 3. In such case, party 3 improves deviating since g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f1; 2g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g and g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 2. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 2g has to be bottom ranked for party 3. In such case, party 3 can improve deviating since g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f2; 3g : Since g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g and g (f2; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 improves deviating since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g, a contradiction. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 3g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 2g and g (f2; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 2g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for 18

party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 improves deviating since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 2g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 2g, a contradiction. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f1; 3g be a Nash equilibrium. If party 2 deviates, it can achieve either g (f2; 3g ; f12g ; f1; 2g) = f2; 3g or g (f2; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 2g. Thus, f1; 3g has to be stable since otherwise party 2 would improve deviating. Then, by Corollary 1, coalition f1; 3g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 3, and bottom ranked for party 2. However, it implies that party 2 improves, a contradiction. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 2g : Since g (f1; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 3g and g (f2; 3g ; f1; 2g ; f1; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 2. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 2g has to be bottom ranked for party 3. In such case, party 3 improves deviating since g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g. Hence, the described pro…le of messages cannot be a Nash equilibrium. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 2g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f1; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f1; 3g and g (f2; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 2. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 2g has to be bottom ranked for party 3. In such case, party 3 improves deviating since g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) where g(m) = f1; 2g : Since g (f1; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f1; 3g and g (f2; 3g ; f1; 3g ; f1; 2g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f1; 2g has to be top ranked for party 1 and party 2. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f1; 2g has to be bottom ranked for party 3. In such case party 3 improves deviating since g (f2; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, a contradiction. Let m = (f2; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 3g) where g(m) = f1; 3g : Since g (f1; 2g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 2g and g (f2; 3g ; f2; 3g ; f2; 3g) = f2; 3g, to guarantee that m is a Nash equilibrium, f2; 3g has to be top ranked for party 2 and party 3. Then, by Corollary 1 coalition f2; 3g has to be bottom ranked for party 1. In such case, party 1 improves deviating since g (f1; 2g ; f2; 3g ; f1; 3g) = f1; 2g, a contradiction.

19

References [1] Amorós P., Corchón L.C. and Moreno B. (2002) The Scholarship Assignment Problem. Games and Economic Behavior 38, 1-18. [2] Aragonès E. (2007a) Government Formation in a Two-dimensional Policy Space. International Journal of Game Theory 35 (2) 151-184. [3] Aragonès E. (2007b) The Key Party in the Catalan Government. Spanish Economic Review 9, 249-271. [4] Austen-Smith D. and Banks J. (1988) Elections, Coalitions, and Legislative Outcomes. American Political Science Review 82 (2) 405-422. [5] Banks J. and Duggan J. (2006) A General Bargaining Model of Legislative Policy-making. Quarterly Journal of Political Science 1, 49-85. [6] Banerjee S., Konishi H. and Sönmez T. (2001) Core in a Simple Coalition Formation Game. Social Choice and Welfare 18, 135-153. [7] Baron D.P. and Ferejohn J. (1989) Bargaining in Legislatures. American Political Science Review 83 (4), 1181-2006. [8] Baron D.P. (1991) A Spatial Bargaining Theory of Government Formation in Parliamentary Systems. American Political Science Review 85, 137-164. [9] Bloch F. (1996) Sequential Formation of Coalitions in Games with Externalities and Fixed Payo¤ Division. Games and Economic Behavior 14, 90-123. [10] Bernheim B.D., Peleg B. and Whinston M.D.(1987) Coalition-Proof Nash Equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory 42, 1-12. [11] Bogomolnaia A. and Jackson M.O. (2002) The Stability of Hedonic coalition Structures. Games and Economic Behavior 38, 201-230. [12] Carroll R. and Cox G.W. (2007) The Logic of Gamson’s Law: Preelection Coalitions and Portfolio Allocations. American Journal of Political Science, 51 (2), 300-313.

20

[13] Diermeier D., Eraslan H. and Merlo A. (2003) A Structural Model of Government Formation. Econometrica, 71 (1), 27-70. [14] Fréchette F., Kagel J. and Morelli M. (2005) Gamson’s Law versus Noncooperative Bargaining Theory. Games and Economic Behavior 51 (2) 365-390. [15] Grossman G.M. and Helpman E. (1996) Electoral competition and special interest politics. Review of Economic Studies 63, 265-286. [16] Harsanyi J. C. and Selten R.A. (1972) Generalized Nash Solution for Two-Person Bargaining Games with Incomplete Information. Management Science, 18 (5), 80-106. [17] Hurwicz L. (1972) On information decentralized systems. In: McGuire CB, Radner R, Decision and organization. North Holland, Amsterdam. [18] Jackson M.O. (2001) A Crash Course in Implementation Theory. Social Choice and Welfare 18, 655-708. [19] Jackson M.O. and Moselle B. (2002) Coalition and Party Formation in a Legislative Voting Games. Journal of Economic Theory 103, 49-87. [20] Kirchsteiger G. and Puppe C. (1997) On the Formation of Political Coalitions. Journal of Institutional Economics 153, 293-319. [21] Le Breton M., Ortuño-Ortin I., and Weber S. (2008) Gamson’s Law and Hedonic Games. Social Choice and Welfare 30 (1), 57-67. [22] Maskin E. (1977) Nash Equilibrium and Welfare Optimality. mimeo, MIT. [23] Müller W.C. and Str;m K. (2000) Coalition Governments in Western Europe. Oxford University Press. [24] Plott C.R. (1967) A Notion of Equilibrium and its possibility under Majority Rule, American Economic Review 57 (4) 787-806. [25] Rijt J.W. van der (2008) An Alternative Model of the Formation of Political Coalitions, Theory and Decision, forthcoming.

21

[26] Saari D.G. (1997) The Generic Existence of a Core for q-rules. Economic Theory 9, 219-60. [27] Serrano R. (1995) A market to implement the core. Journal of Economic Theory 67, 285-294. [28] Serrano R. and Vohra R. (1997) Non-cooperative Implementation of the Core. Social Choice and Welfare 14, 513-525. [29] Scho…eld N. (1983) Generic Instability of Majority Rule, Review of Economic Studies 50, 695-705. [30] von Neumann J. and Morgenstern O. (1944) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton: Princeton University. [31] Yi S.S. (2003) Endogenous Formation of Economic Coalitions: A survey of the Partition Function Approach in C. Carraro (ed.) The Endogenous Formation of Economic Coalitions. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 80-124.

22

Stable Coalition$Governments under Weighted ...

Stable Coalition$Governments under. Weighted Political Agreements! M. Socorro Puy. Dpto. Teoría e Historia Económica. Universidad de Málaga, Spain. March 26, 2009. Abstract. Once elections have taken place, we consider that three parties can hold offi ce in the form of two$party coalitions. Political parties are both: offi ...

212KB Sizes 0 Downloads 171 Views

Recommend Documents

A Stable Estimator for the Information Matrix under EM
data scores that are readily available from running the EM algorithm. ... Both real and simulated data are used to ..... The stock market is undoubtedly subject.

Affinity Weighted Embedding
Jan 17, 2013 - contain no nonlinearities (other than in the feature representation in x and y) they can be limited in their ability to fit large complex datasets, and ...

Investing before Stable Matching
†Universitat Aut`onoma de Barcelona and Barcelona GSE, email: .... 4The complete market is the benchmark situation where investments and partnerships are ...

Weighted Automata Algorithms - Semantic Scholar
A finite-state architecture for tokenization and grapheme-to- phoneme conversion in multilingual text analysis. In Proceedings of the ACL. SIGDAT Workshop, Dublin, Ireland. ACL, 1995. 57. Stephen Warshall. A theorem on Boolean matrices. Journal of th

Web's Gems Stable
Web's Gems Stable. 2005 to 2011 Yearly Results. Win Percentage: 29%. Win, Place, Show Percentage: 59%. Horse. Starts 1st 2nd. 3rd. 4th 5th+. Share of .... Iron Boy. 5. 3. 1. 0. 1. 0. $7,350. Lite Brigade. 10. 4. 5. 1. 0. 0. $38,056. Miltos Express. 3

Contractually Stable Alliances
ranking followed by information technology (184 alliances) and automotive (53 ... We would like to thank two anonymous referees and the associate editor for ...

Contractually stable networks
Oct 26, 2012 - Requiring the consent of coalition members may help to reconcile stability and efficiency in some classical models of network formation. Keywords Networks · Coalition structures · Contractual stability · Strong efficiency. JEL Class

Chronic Stable Angina
Jun 16, 2005 - coronary artery disease.9,10,13 Data from the Wom- .... reasonable to begin therapy with agents from any .... rate recovery should also.

Stable Matching With Incomplete Information
Lastly, we define a notion of price-sustainable allocations and show that the ... KEYWORDS: Stable matching, incomplete information, incomplete information ... Our first order of business is to formulate an appropriate modification of ...... whether

Weighted Bench Dip.pdf
the movement. Forearms should always be pointing down. 3. 4. ... stay there throughout the movement. Page 1 of 1. Weighted Bench Dip.pdf. Weighted Bench ...

Weighted Automata Algorithms - Semantic Scholar
The mirror image of a string x = x1 ···xn is the string xR = xnxn−1 ··· x1. Finite-state transducers are finite automata in which each transition is augmented with an ...

Weighted Grade Scale.pdf
Page 1 of 1. Weighted Grade Scale. Grade Regular vs. Weighted. A 4.0 = 4.5. A- 3.667 = 4.125. B+ 3.33 = 3.75. B 3.0 = 3.375. B- 2.667 = 3.0. C+ 2.33 = 2.625.

Stable Marriage and Search Frictions
Jul 5, 2012 - Define x(m,m) = 1− ∑ w∈W x(m,w) and x(w,w) = 1− ∑ m∈M x(m,w). .... Definition (Steady State Matching) .... Utilities given by the bi-matrix w1.

Generalizing relevance weighted LDA
Rapid and brief communication ... Key Lab of Optoelectronic Technology and Systems of Education Ministry of China, Chongqing University, Chongqing 400044 ...

Weighted hamming distance:Image webservices with hashcode - IJRIT
Abstract— Scalable image search based on visual similarity has been an active topic .... database. We name this weighted distance as query-adaptive Hamming ...

Affinity Weighted Embedding - JMLR Workshop and Conference ...
39.2%. 5.2. ImageNet. ImageNet (Deng et al., 2009) is a large scale image dataset organized according to WordNet (Fellbaum, 1998). Con- cepts in WordNet ...

Learning with Weighted Transducers - Research at Google
b Courant Institute of Mathematical Sciences and Google Research, ... over a vector space are the polynomial kernels of degree d ∈ N, Kd(x, y)=(x·y + 1)d, ..... Computer Science, pages 262–273, San Francisco, California, July 2008. Springer-.

INSTABILITY OF WEIGHTED COMPOSITION ...
We provide sharp instability bounds. 1. Introduction. Let K denote the field of real or complex numbers. Let C(X) stand for the Banach space of all K-valued continuous functions defined on a compact Hausdorff X and equipped with its usual supremum no

Joint Weighted Nonnegative Matrix Factorization for Mining ...
Joint Weighted Nonnegative Matrix Factorization for Mining Attributed Graphs.pdf. Joint Weighted Nonnegative Matrix Factorization for Mining Attributed Graphs.

Procedurally Fair and Stable Matching
stable matchings in which he/she is not matched to his/her best partner in the reduced set of .... is better off as well, then we would expect this mutually beneficial “trade” to be carried out, rendering the given ... private schools and univers

Thermodynamically Stable Blue Phases
Apr 13, 2010 - resurgence of interest in the area. In the latter ... energetically unfavorable due to high elastic distortion. ... If the energy saving from the DTCs out- .... to take into account specific different values of these co- ... 2 (color o

Stable and efficient coalitional networks - Springer Link
Sep 9, 2012 - made to the coalitional network needs the consent of both the deviating players and their original coalition partners. Requiring the consent of ...

A more stable outlook
Lippo Malls Indonesia Retail Trust ... Other Long-term Liabilities. 12 ..... Commercial Trust, CapitaLand Mall Trust, Croesus Retail Trust, First REIT, Frasers ..... Good, MBKET – Good, MC – Very Good, MCOT – Very Good, MEGA – Good, MINT -.

Clustering Graphs by Weighted Substructure Mining
Call the mining algorithm to obtain F. Estimate θlk ..... an advanced graph mining method with the taxonomy of labels ... Computational Biology Research Center.