The Historical Socrates and Athenian Democracy Gregory Vlastos Political Theory, Vol. 11, No. 4. (Nov., 1983), pp. 495-516. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0090-5917%28198311%2911%3A4%3C495%3ATHSAAD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-2 Political Theory is currently published by Sage Publications, Inc..

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sage.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

http://www.jstor.org Sat Aug 25 08:12:34 2007

CLASSICAL GREEK POLITICAL THOUGHT I. THE HISTORICAL SOCRATES A N D ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY1 GREGORY VLASTOS

University of California, Berkeley

shall argue for two theses: I. In his own time and place Socrates was perceived as a political subversive and this was a weighty reason for his prosecution and condemnation, though by no means the only reason: the formal charges of disbelieving the gods of the state, lntroduclng new divinities, and corrupting the youth were fully as welghty. 11. This public perccptlon of Socrates was a mlsperception: he had not been the crypto-oligarch many had thought he was.

If I had ample time I would divide it equally between the two theses, for they are equally material to the understanding of Socrates'historical relation t o his native city Since my time is short I shall devote by far the greater part of it to argument for the second thesis, for here-in the argument for this thesis, not in the thesis itself-I have something new to offer which calls for extensive elucidation, far more than will be possible within the limits of my time-schedule. Since the truth of this second thesis presupposes that of the first, that is where I must begin. Consider the following well-known text: T I Aeschlnes, Contra Timarchum, 173: "Men of Athens, you executed Socrates the s o p h ~ sbecause t he was shown to have educated Critlas, one of the Thlrty who subverted the democracy."

What this shows is that half a century after Socrates'death alot-selected jury-a fair sample of Athenian opinion at the time: a pollster picking EDITOR'S NOTE: The leading articles by VIaslos and Raafaub were originally presented at the Conference for Political Thought's inrernarional meeting on Greek Polirical Thought, held a! the Graduare Center of City University of New York, April 1983. Two additional essays from the conference will appear in rhe February issue. POLITICAL THEORY, Vol. 1 1 No. 4, November 1983 495-516 O 1983 Sage Publications, Inc.

496

POLITICAL THEORY I NOVEMBER 1983

h ~ s ample could not have done much better-was expected to agree without argument that Socrates had been put to death because he had been the teacher of the man who stood in the public mind for the most savagely antidemocratic regime Athens had ever known. And now consider how a sophist's relation to a powerful politician who had been his pupil was popularly regarded at the time: T2 Plutarch, Pericles 4,l: "Most people say that [Pericles) teacher of music was Damon. Now Damon seems to have been a consummate sophist. He had used music as a screen to h ~ d he ~ cleverness s from the public. In his relation to Pericles he was in politlcs what a coach and tralner is to an athlete." (Cf. also Anstotle, Ath. Pol. 27, 4).2

What to us seems so preposterous-that a brilliant statesman's role in public affairs could be accounted for by the personal effect of a sophist's teaching-was evidently not thought at all implausible at, or near, Socrates'own lifetime: the fourth-century historians on whom Plutarch is drawing in T2, Aristotle among them, find no difficulty in believing that the radical reforms by which Pericles changed the course of Athenian history had been put into his head by a sophist who had taught him m u ~ i c . 2Aeschines ~ and his Athenian audience would have found no greater difficulty in believing that Critias' sensational political career had been instigated by a sophist who had taught him rhetoric. We thus have evidence from an unimpeachable source-an orator untlnctured by philosophy, caring nothing one way or the other about it, and having no partisan axe to grind by representing Socrates as a pro-oligarchic ~deologue-that Socrates, because of his association with Critias, was believed half a century after his death to have been a breeder of subversion. It is a reasonable inference that the same would be true at the time of Socrates' trial, when Critias' crimes were so much more fresh in everyone's mind: no less sinister a construction would be likely to be put on that association and, we may add, also on his association with Alcibiades, a notorious contemner of democracy (Thuc. 6, 89, 5). T3 Xenophon, Mem. 1 , 2, 12: "But the accuser said that Critias and

Alcibiades, having associated w ~ t hSocrates, did great evil to the city."

For this inference we have excellent confirmation: T4 Xenophon, Mem. 1, 2, 9: "But, by Zeus, said the accuser, he made his

associates despise the established laws, saying it was silly to appoint the

Vlastos / SOCRATES A N D ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

497

c~ty'smagistrates by lot, when no one would want to use a lot-selected pilot or builder or flute-player or any other [craftsman] for work In whlch mlstakes are far less disastrous than those whlch concern the c~ty."

In marked contrast to every other charge against Socrates rehearsed in the Memorabilia, to all of which Xenophon responds with voluble apologetics, this charge Xenophon must think so true and so firmly entrenched in his readers'minds that he does not say a word to rebut it: he drops it like a hot potato. S o unless there were direct evidence to the contrary, the first part of my first thesis would stand: Socrates was perceived as a politically subversive teacher, and this perception of him would have certainly weighed strongly in the motives of the prosecution and in the minds of many of the jurors who had voted for his conviction. And there is no evidence to the contrary As has long been recognized, the fact that the imputation of subversion does not surface in the formal indictment does not constitute such evidence, for this fact is perfectly explicable by the amnesty to substantiate the imputation in court Socrates'tutorial link to Critias or other leaders of the oligarchic coup would have had to be rehearsed, and this would have been a violation of the amnesty Thus Socrates could only have been formally indicted on charges which either were not political at all-not believing in the gods of the state and introducing new divinities-or only indirectly political: corrupting the youth.3 That these charges were not just window-dressing-the mere "pretexts" Burnet called them (Greek Philosophy, Thales to Plato [London, 19141, 189)-is what I claim in the second part of my first thesis. That this claim is true is abundantly clear from the Platonic Apology (22E-23E = T6):Socrates had provoked powerful enmities by blasting the credibility of big mouths in Athens and they, retaliating, had done their best to get people to believe that the Aristophanic caricature, a comic extravaganza, had been in fact the ugly truth. We thus have evidence that Socrates was prosecuted and convicted both as impious speculator and shyster rhetorician, on the one hand, and as a fomenter of oligarchic sentiment, on the other. Scholars like R. Hackforth (The Composltlon of Pluto's Apology [Cambridge, 19331, 73ff.), who adduced evidence of the former as though it constituted evidence against the latter were simply confused: there is no inconsistency between the two, since in the public image of Socrates the pestilential sophist was the subversive. Now to my second thesis. I maintain that the perception of Socrates as a pro-oligarchic ideologist who aroused hostility towards the Athenian constitution in his associates was completely false: false it

498

POLITICAL THEORY I NOVEMBER 1983

must have been if Socrates preferred that constitution to every other in the contemporary world-which is precisely what we are told in one of the most familiar, yet least heeded, passages in the Platonic corpus: Crito 51C4-53C8. Of all the commentators consulted, only oneGeorge Grote, in his monumental work, Pluto and the Other Companlons of Socrates (reprint of the 1888 edition, New York [1973], 430-431)-has discerned what I take t o be the true import of this passage: that "it is a piece of rhetoric imbued with the most genuine spirit of constitional democracy"; that here "Socrates is made to express the feelings and repeat the language of a devoted democratical patriot." Grote must have thought that this would be so evident to anyone who would but read the passage that he offered no argument at all for this interpretation of the text. Since the passage has been read very differently by other scholars I must supply the argument, even at the risk of laboring the obvious. Socrates is explaining why he must decline the opportunity Crito has offered him t o escape. His explanation is put into a discourse by the personified laws of Athens. Since the latter are Socrates' mouthpiecewhat they say is what he makes them say-the sentiments they impute to him must be his own3* I shall, therefore, report them as such. The sentiment on which they dwell at greatest length is his affection for Athens and its laws-a sentiment that has the intensity of a romantic attachment: T5 Cr. 52BI-CI: "0Socrates, we have strong proof that both we and the c ~ t y have been pleasing to you. For you would not have been, above other Athenians, exceedingly constant In your residence In the clty, if it were not exceedingly pleaslng to you. Not even for a festlval did you ever go out of Athens, except once to the Isthmlan games-nowhere else, except on military servlce; nor did you make any out-of-town vlslts, like other folk, nor did the des~reever seize you to know some other ctty, some other laws: you have been sat~sfiedw ~ t hus and with our city."

Like an infatuated lover, Socrates can hardly bring himself to part a single day from his beloved Athens. What is it that keeps him so glued to it over the years? The only thing he mentions here is Athens' laws. The city and its laws appear conjunctively at the start ("both we and the city have been pleasing to you") and then again at the conclusion("you have been satisfied with us and with our city"). The conjunction is maintained in the sequel:

Vlastos / SOCRATES AND ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

499

T6 52c1-3: "So Intensely did you prefer us (houto sphodra hemas hSrou) and agree to conduct your CIVIC life In accordance wlth us that, among other thlngs, you had children In ~t(scil. the city), whlch shows that the clty pleased you (hi% areskousTs sol tes poleos)."

I translate helrou (literally 'chose') In Houro sphodra hemas helrou by "preferred". that t h ~ 1s s what 1s meant 1s clear both from the context (the choice In favor of the laws of Athens (hFmas hpirou) 1s dep~cted throughout the passage4 as expressing a preference for ~ t slaws over those of other cit~es)and from the qualifying adverb (not choice per se, but preference, could be properly spoken of as "intense"). S o the same dec~s~on-to ralse a family In Athens-1s v~ewedfirst as e v ~ d e n c ~ nag preference for the city's laws ("so Intensely did you prefer us") and then agaln, w ~ t h o u any t Interjected explanation, as e v ~ d e n c ~ hls n g preference for the city ("wh~chshows that the clty pleased you."). The very structure of the sentence shows that the object of Socrates' preference 1s the same In each case: What pleases Socrates in the c ~ t 1s y its laws; the laws speak of the c ~ t yas "our city" (T5 above) and proceed to ask: "whom would a c ~ t yplease w~thoutthe laws?'Y Now what 1s ~tIn the laws of Athens that Socrates prefers to the laws of "every other c ~ t yGreek , o r barbanan," Including the laws of Sparta and Crete6 and of Thebes and Megara?' What 1s ~tthat sets off Athens most dramat~callyfrom all four of those "well-governed'% c~ties?In respect of ~ t c~vil s and c r ~ m ~ nlaw a l Athens would differ little from ~ t s ne~ghbors-scarcely at all from Megara, a h~ghlycommerc~alcity, whose economy, and hence ~ t sc~villaw, would be in all essent~als ~ d e n t ~ cwa l~ t hthat of Athens. The salient difference-the one that would leap to the eye of any Greekjuxtaposlng Athens agalnst that quartet of c~t~es-would be In the area of c o n s t ~ t u t ~ o n law a l 9 In the Athen~an const~tutiondemocracy reached ~ t sa pogee In fifth-century Greece, while each of those four constltutlons stood as clearly for oligarchyextreme In the case of the Spartan and Cretan constltutlons, moderate In the case of the Theban and Megar~an.S o while no mentlon 1s made of e ~ t h e dr emocracy or oligarchy anywhere in the passage, there can be no doubt that Socrates' preference for Athen~anlaw 1s a preference for Athens'democratlc constltutlon. Each of the four oligarch~esSocrates hails as "well-governedw-as well he m ~ g h tIn the case of Sparta and Crete, exemplars of law-governed, law-respect~ng,law-observ~ngconduct throughout the Greek world (cf. Hdt. 7,104). If Socrates were

500

POLITICAL THEORY / NOVEMBER 1983

Athens on this score with Sparta and Crete or even with Thebes and Megara, he would certainly prefer any of them to Athens for, as shall see, he thinks the A t h e n ~ a nrecord of law-observance deplorably low. Thus h ~ preference s for Athen~anover Spartan, Cretan, Theban and Megarian law could only be a preference for the democratic form of government over the leading specimens of oligarchy He ranks the ultrademocratic constitutlon of the undisc~plinedAthen~ansabove the oligarchic constitutlon of the disc~plined("well-governed") Thebans and Megarians and the still more undemocrat~cconstitutlon of the still more disciplined Spartans and Cretans. Can we take him at h ~ word? s If so, the case for my second thesis has been made. Is there any reason why we can't? To deny or doubt Socrates' preference for the Athen~anconstitut~onwhlch 1s expressed so forcefully In the Crlto we would have to be convinced of one or the other or both of the following: comparing

1. That this preference 1s contradicted by other sentiments expressed by Socrates elsewhere In Plato's Socrat~cdialogues.10

2. That it 1s contradicted by opinlons volced by Socrates in Xenophon, our other major source, and that we have evidence independent of both Xenophon and Plato for rating Xenophon's credibility on this polnt more h~ghlythan Plato's.

I shall argue that Plato's testimony In the Crlto passage, as Interpreted above, is unassailable on either of these grounds and should, therefore, be accepted as true. On the first of those two points I can be fairly brief. No harsher indictment of Athen~anpublic conduct has survlved than the one Plato puts into Socrates' mouth in the Apology. T7 Ap. 3 ID: "Fellow Athen~ans,you should know that, if I had tried to do politlcs (prattern tapolitiko) long before thls, I would have perished long before t h ~ s , without dolng any good either to you or to myself. Don't be Incensed at me for telling you the truth. There Isn't a man who would survlve if he really set h~mselft o oppose you or any other mult~tude,trylng to block the perpetration of many lnjustlces and illegalit~esIn the c~ty."

He 1s telling his fellow-citizens that thelr political life is such a jungle of lawlessness and injustice that ajust man who gets into it determined to fight forjustice is virtually signing his own death warrant. In the Gorglas there 1s a no less savage attack on democratic leadersh~p.Its theme IS that in Athenian politlcs the ticket to power 1s flattery of the demos. This 1s the first thing Socrates tells Callicles at the start of thelr debate, barely managing to avoid the extreme rudeness, the gross insult, of the

Vlastos / SOCRATES AND ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

501

imputation by resorting to banter, ringing the changes on an atrocious pun: Callicles is as ingratiating to the Athenian demos as to his young inamorato whose name is "Demos". T8 Gorg. 481 Dl-El: "It strikes me that you and I have had the same experience-each of us has two loves: In my case, Alcib~ades, son of Clin~as,and philosophy; In yours, the AthenIan demos and Pyrilampes' son, Demos. I perceive that, though you are very smart, whatever your boy-love asserts, however he says thlngs are, you can't bear to contradict h~m-you change up and down. S o too In the Assembly, if you say someth~ngand the AthenIan " demos says it ~ s n ' so, t you turn around and say whatever they want

And Socrates then picks the four greatest Athenian statesmen of the fifth century-Themistocles, Miltiades, Cimon, Peric1es"-and has the brass to say that they were no better than the current crop of demagogues, indeed worse: those giants were more servile (diakonikoterol, 517B) than are the shrimps who lead us now. That this judgment is harshly biased, intemperate in the extreme, should not pass unnoticed: see Thucydides on Pericles as a corrective (2,65,8). Nor should we fail to notice that Socrates is represented as airing his ferocious critiques of Athens in very public contexts. In the Gorgras he has a considerable audience: Gorgias' Athenian clique has turned out in force along with many others. In the Apology there are 501 jurors and who knows how many hundred others in the audience. Socrates advertises sentiments which in the mind of malicious (or even merely thoughtless) hearers would more than suffice to convict him. of oligarchic partisanship. Much less would have sufficed to tar him with this brush. Isocrates, who had done no more to bait the superdemocrats than advocate a return to the conservative democracy which his fancy locates in Athens' earlier history, says he had been warned that T9 Isocr. Areop. 3 7 "I ran the r ~ s keven , while glvlng you the best adv~ce,of belng thought an enemy of the people (mrsodFmos) and of seeking to turn the crty Into an oligarchy."

But let us not lose track of the main point in the present argument. The question is whether or not, in putting into Socrates' mouth those bitter attacks on Athens' political life in the Apology and the Gorgras, Plato is undermining the credibility of his assurance in the Crrto that Socrates finds the constitution of Athens "exceedingly pleasing" to him and prefers it to that of "any other city, Greek or barbarian." The answer, surely is that he does not. Certainly there is no contradiction. If I believe that the laws of city A are better than those of city B, I incur no

502

POLITICAL THEORY / NOVEMBER 1983

inconsistency in saying that city B observes its laws more faithfully than does city A. There is nothing wrong with A's laws, I might explain; the fault lies with the people who abuse them. This is the view Socrates takes of the wrong done to him by the jury that condemned him. At the conclusion of the discourse of the laws in the Crlto, they say to him: T I 0 Cr 54B-C."You will depart, wronged not by us, the laws, but by men."

For the wrong of his condemnation Socrates blames men, not Athenian law This is not because he thinks that law perfect (cf. Ap. 37A7-Bl), but because he thinks it a reasonable law under which fair-minded judges could and should have acquitted him. By the same token he could have held that the lnnocent people who were terrorized by political blackmailers ("sycophants") in Athens are wronged by men, not by laws, and that when Athenian politicans betray the high trust of their office by resort to flattery, it is their personal depravity, not that of the law, which is to blame: if they had true integrity they would rather die than flatter. Thus neither in the Apology nor in the Gorgras-nor, I may add, anywhere in Plato's Socratic dialogues-does Socrates rescind that personal vote of confidence he gives the Athenian constitution in the Crrto. If we were to agree with Burnet that Socrates is "an irreconcilable opponent of the Periclean democracy" (188), with Heinrich Maier that for Socrates "democracy is the most perverse of all forms of government" (Sokrares [Tubingen, 19 131, 417), with W.K.C. Guthrie that Socrates held views w h ~ c h"contravened the whole basls of Greek democracy" (History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. 111 [Cambridge, 19691, 410), we would have to d o so in defiance of Plato's testimony T o support such views we would have to look exclusively to Xenophon.12 Our star passage would be the following: T I I Xenophon, Mem. 3,9,10: "He sald that k ~ n g sand rulers are not those who hold the sceptre, nor those elected by chance persons nor those who owe thelr power to force or deception; but those who know how to rule. For once ~twas granted that ~t1s for the ruler to order what should be done and for the ruled to obey, he proceeded to polnt out that on a s h ~ he p who has knowledge 1s the ruler, while the ship-owner and all others o n board obey the one who has knowledge [and so too In the case of farming, treatment of the slck, physlcal tralnlng, wool-spinning: those who have knowledge rule.]"

Xenophon is adverting here to Socrates' cardinal doctrine that knowledge "is"l3 virtue, taking it to have a direct political import, which he understands as follows: there is a form of knowledge whose possession 1s

Vlastos 1 SOCRATES A N D ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

503

as necessary a qualification for serving as ruler in a polis as is knowledge of navigation for being the captain of a ship o r knowledge of agriculture for serving as the manager of a productive farm. This knowledge, which Socrates calls "the royal art",I4 is the sine q u a non of political authority; a ruler who lacks it is afake; his authority has n o legitimacy What is the politicall5 content of this art-what is it knowledge of, That it is knowledge of ruling is uninformatively tautologous. What we need to learn is what the ruler must know in order to know how to rule. Though there is n o direct answer to this in Xenophon, we can derive it from what we learn there of Socrates' view of the quintessential attribute of the good ruler. O n this Xenophon is very clear: T I 2 M em.3,2,4: "When [Socrates] inqulred what 1s the vlrtue of a good ruler, he s happy." str~ppedaway everything but thls: maklng h ~ followers

And how Xenophon understands Socrates'conception of the happiness (eudazmonza) which the good ruler procures for his subjects we can see n o less clearly in the analysis of the function of a citizen which Xenophon puts into Socrates' mouth, i.e., of what each citizen would contribute to the city if his civic activities were well directed: T I 3 Mem.4, 6, 14: "Let us lnqulre what IS the funct~onof a good cltizen. In the admlnlstrat~onof moneys IS not the superlor cltlzen he who makes the c ~ t y r~cher? I n war, 1s ~tnot he who makes her prevail over her enem~es? In I n public embass~es,he who makes fr~endsfor her In lieu of enemles? oratory, he who allays CIVIC strife and produces harmony?"

Thus what Socrates takes to be the elements of civic happiness, according t o Xenophon, are material affluence, military supremacy, good relations with other cities, good relations among the citizens themselves. These are the things the ruler must know himself if he is to direct his subjects' efforts towards their attainment. He must have knowledge of the various branches of statecraft-of public finance, of military science, of the arts ofdiplomacy, of the rhetoric of civic amity 16 Would Athenian democracy pass muster when inspected from this point of view? Its most distinctive political institution, election by lot, would suffice to d a m n it. Judged as a device t o snag for the offices of the polis those and only those who possess the "royal art," election by lot would strike anyone as the "silly" thing Polycrates had charged and Xenophon had conceded Socrates thought it t o be, as we saw in T4 above. One might try t o extenuate the offense of democracy to the "royal art" by arguing that those elected by this device were the magistrates-subordinate officers of the administration. But this would

504

POLITICAL THEORY / NOVEMBER 1983

overlook the fact that not only they were elected by lot. S o was the Council-the probouleutic and executive committee of the sovereign Assembly And s o were all the dicasteries, whose supreme judicial authority was on a par with that of the sovereign Assembly. Aristotle underlines the significance of their power: TI4 A th. Pol. 9, 1: "When the people have sovereignty In the votlng [in the courts1,they become sovereign In the c o n s t ~ t u t ~ o n . "

T o be sure, for the appointment of the generals-the most important executive officers of the state-Athens resorted to an alternative procedure which it shared with the oligarchies: election by show of hands in the Assembly. In theeyes of Xenophon's Socrates this would be a redeeming feature-but not redeeming enough, given his low opinion of the intellectual level of the democratic electorate. This is how he talks about ~twhen trying to persuade his friend Charmides to speak before the Assembly: T I 5 M em. 3,7,5-6: "You speak unabashed and unlnt~mldatedIn the company of the most Intelligent and capable people, and yet you are scared to speak In the company of the feeblest and most s t u p ~ dOf . whom are you frightened? The fullers, cobblers, builders, coppersmiths, farmers, merchants and those who traffic in the market, carlng for nothlng but to buy cheap and sell dear-for ~t 1s from all these that the Assembly is made up."

This is not formal doctrine. But it reveals clearly enough what Xenophon takes to be Socrates' attitude t o the working classes of Athens: t o the people who make up the great bulk of the Assembly he refers as "the feeblest and most stupid" members of the civic body In another well-known passage we see how, according to Xenophon, Socrates feels about that largest single segment of the working population w h ~ c hhe calls "banausoi'-a highly emotive term which no one would apply to them to their face, unless one wanted to insult them: T I 6 O econom~cus4 ,2: "The so-called 'banauslc'occupations are badly spoken of and, qulte naturally, are held in utter contempt in our cltles. For they ruln the bodies of those who work In them and of thelr foremen, forcing them Into sedentary indoor work. And as thelr bodies become womanlsh then souls too become much more debilitated. Moreover these so-called banauslc crafts allow no le~surefor attention to one's friends and to the clty, so that such people are thought bad both In dealing wlth frlends and In defending thelr fatherland. And in some cities, particularly those whlch are good in war, cltlzens are not even allowed to work In banauslc craftsW(cf.also Oec. 6.4-9).

Vlastos / SOCRATES AND ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

505

Bypassing the folkloric psychophysiology of the supposed effects of door sedentary work on the body and therewith on the soul, let us concentrate on the remark that banausic occupations allow no leuure. Xenophon's Socrates thinks of them as closing off to the banausos that area in which the upperclass Greek locates the intrinsically worthwhile activities of his life-music and poetry, sport, friendship, politics. We can see in Aristotle where this line of thought takes us when pushed further by a powerful thinker. It divides the population of the polis into the "necessary" people, as Aristotle calls them, and the "beautiful" people, the "worthwhile" people (kaloi kagathol, chrestoi), as they like to call themselves. It follows that when the purpose of the polis is conceived in the Greek way-to realize the good life for its citizenscivic status should be limited, so far as possible, to the beautiful people, and should include as few as possible of the necessary ones: T17 Arlstotle, Pol. 1278A7-13: "The best polis will not make the banausos a c~tizen.But if he too IS to be a cltlzen, then what we prev~ouslys a ~ dwas the clt~zen'svlrtue will not be for everyone-for every freeman-but only for those who are exempt from the necessary servlces w h ~ c hslaves perform for banausor and thFtes for the public." ~ndiv~duals,

This is the most fundamental point on which democrats and oligarchs divide. Democracy stands for inclusive citizenship-inclusive of banausoz: all Athenians born of native Athenians are citizens of Athens. Oligarchy stands for exclusive citizenship-exclusive of banausor, so far as possiblel7. of all Thebans born of native Thebans half or less would be citizens of Thebes.18 If Socrates had advocated disfranchisement of the banausor-which would have cut Athens'civic rolls by nearly half-he would have declared openly for oligarchy Given Xenophon's apologetic interests, his Socrates cannot be allowed to go so far. But no doubt is left in the reader's mind where Socrates' preference would lie: If the banausoi have civic status they will swarm into the Council and the dicasteries through the lot; they will have the swing-vote there as in the sovereign Assembly; the fate of "the most intelligent and capable" members of the civic body-the only ones who, by the doctrine of the "royal art,"should have any access at all to political office-will be at the mercy of the judgment of the "feeblest and most stupid," entrusted to them by the operation of the lot. In the Socrates of Xenophon's Socratic writings, upon the one hand, and of Plato's Socratic dialogues, on the other, we meet two philosophers whose political sentiments are diametrically opposite. The convictions of Xenophon's Socrates commit him to an

506

POLITICAL THEORY / NOVEMBER 1983

overwhelming preference for oligarchy over democracy Plato's Socrates, though harshly critical of lawless and unjust conduct in the city of his birth, nonetheless prefers the constitution of that city-the most extreme democracy of his world-to that of every other state known t o him, including that of each of the "well-governedn oligarchies he names. Here I must face a powerful argument-so powerful that if I could not produce a completely adequate reply the whole of the foregoing argument would be gutted: "But does not Plato's Socrates also hold the doctrine of the'royal art? Would not this have the same antidemocratic import?" The answer, in a nutshell, is that Plato's Socrates most certainly has a doctrine of the "royal art"; but it is not the same doctrine and has no antidemocratic import. T o see why this is so we must go down to the rock-bottom of Socrates'moral philosophy, the thesis that virtue is knowledge, and face up to the fact that the knowledge Socrates has in view in Plato's Socratic dialogues is exclusively moralknowledge: it has nothing t o d o with knowledge of the instrumentalities of thegood life; it is knowledge of ends or, more precisely, knowledge of the end of the good life, that unique end which is for Plato's Socrates, unlike Xenophon's, the only thing which matters: the perfection of the soul, its moral perfection, on which, for Plato's Socrates, the whole of human happiness depends: TI8 Gorg. 470E8-11: Polus. "What? Is the whole of happ~nessIn that (scil.pardela and justice)?" Socrates. "Yes, Polus, that I S what I say. For I say that the noble and good man and woman is happy, the unjust and wicked wretched."

Every non-moral good-wealth, health, honor, pleasure, life itself-is immaterial for human happiness. Each of these goods is worthless in and of itself (Euthyd. 28 1 D-E); each of them may be evil instead of good unless we know how to use it in the service of moral Improvement: TI9 Euthyd. 288E7-289B2: "Even if we knew how to turn stones Into gold, such knowledge would be worthless. For if we did not know how to use gold, ~t would profit us nothing. Even if there were some knowledge that would make us immortal, if we did not know how to use our ~mmortality,even that would profit us nothing ."

This being as true for our corporate as for our private life, the knowledge which should direct the city is the same as that which should direct each individual man and woman: knowledge of the end, the same end, perfection of soul. Hence the criterion of good statesmanship is

Vlastos / SOCRATES AND ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

507

ability t o assist the people of the city-all of them, not just those who have leisure for the amenities-all the citizens, including, of course, the banauso~,and all the non-citizens as well: everyone in the city, including the slaves. This, Callicles is told in the Gorgias, is how his excellence as a statesman should be judged: T20 Gorg. 515A4-7: "Say, has Callicles made any cltlzen a better man? Is there anyone, cltlzen or alien, freeman or slave, formerly w~ked-unjust, dissolute, ~ntemperate-who has become a good and noble man because of Callicles?"

Can we imagine what a transvaluation of values this Socrates-Plato's, not Xenophon's-presses on his world in telling an upper class Athenian that the criterion of his statesmanship is whether or not it improves the souls of the people of Athens-even the souls ofslaves?l9 In this conception of human virtue the distinction between the "necessary" and the "beautiful" people is wiped out. There are no second-class souls. This is the knowledge-soul-perfecting knowledge-which Plato's Socrates calls "the political art" and "the royal art". the phrases are the same as in Xenophon but their content is radically different, for in Plato they exclude those very competences which, as we saw above,20 are at the heart of the "royal art" for Socrates in Xenophon: T21 Euthyd. 292B4-CI: "As for those other thlngs which might be sald to belong to the political art [= the royal art: 291 B4ff.I-and they are many, e.g. to make the citlzens nch, free [scil. from external domination], undisturbed by factlon: these thrngs have turned out to be nerther good nor evil, while what the cltlzens need, if they are to be benefitted and made happy, 1s to be made wlse-to have [moral] knowledge imparted to them."

For Xenophon's Socrates the royal art is statecraft-mastery of the great instrumentalities of clvic happiness: wealth, military supremacy, good external relations, harmonious internal relations. For Plato's Socrates the royal art is nothing of that sort. It has no more to d o with the art of fiscal prudence, of military science, of shrewd diplomacy, of persuasive oratory, than with the art of making us immortal or of turning stones into gold.*' Needless to say, we cannot run acity without economists, generals, ambassadors, orators, and other masters of the instrumentalities: public doctors, architects, engineers, and so forth. But all these specialists should d o their job under the direct~onof the royal art, whose sole competence is moral knowledge: expertise In determining how the instrumentalities of statecraft can be used best in the Interest of moral perfection.22

508

P O L I T I C A L T H E O R Y / N O V E M B E R 1983

This wi'sdom cannot be monopolized by members of the city's upper crust, as lt has to be for Xenophon's Socrates, for if it were, moral virtue could only belong to few, while for Plato's Socrates it must belong to everyone: everyone is called upon to make perfection of soul the supreme concern of his o r her personal existence-everyone, alien and cltizen, slave and freeman, female and male. This is the conviction which turns Plato's Socrates-not Xenophon's-into a street philosopher, which no philosopher had been before him and none would be after him, except perhaps the Cynics, and they only as his spiritual grandchildren: Socrates begat Antisthenes and Antisthenes begat Diogenes the Dog. The call "perfect your soul" goes out to everyone, delivered personally by Plato's Socrates to "anyone he runs into" in the market or on the street: T22 Apol. 29D-30B: "I shall not cease p h i l o s o p h ~ z ~ n ga n d e x h o r t ~ n g you and expostulating wlth each o n e of you I happen t o run into, saylng t o hlm In m y customary way: '0 best of men, A t h e n ~ a ncitlzen , of the greatest city, most highly reputed for its wisdom and power, are you not ashamed t o be concerned t o make as much money as possible and for reputation and prestige, while for w ~ s d o mand truth and for the greatest possible Improvement of your soul you have n o care o r worry?' These things I will say t o anyone I run Into, young o r old, alien o r cltlzen

The conception of the royal art which Xenophon ascribes to Socrates is oligarchic in the literal sense of that word: in principle, it belongs only tofew-those few who have had the leisure and other opportunities to acquire knowledge of statecraft-assuring them that, in virtue of their possession of that knowledge, they and they alone are the legitimate rulers of the city Should I say that the conception of that art which Plato ascribes to Socrates is democratic in the same literal sense-it belongs t o the demos? No, for that would understate its scope: it is for every person, including all those who did not belong to the Athenian demos-aliens no less than citizens, slaves no less than freemen, women no less than men.*3 All are invited to seek it. But who, if any, will come to possess it remains in doubt. S o my argument should hew strictly to the terms of my second thesls, whose limited scope should not be missed. Let me remind you of the terms in which I formulated that thesis at the start: the perception of Socrates as a crypto-oligarch is a misperception. And let me recall the way I sized up the import of the positive evidence for that thesls I have offered in t h ~ article-the s only positive evidence for it there is: the three texts in the Crito. There Socrates declares his personal preference for the constitution of his

Vlastos / SOCRATES A N D ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

509

native city-the most democratic constitution the mind of man had yet conceived. But he produces no theory to justify that preference-not even the adumbration of a theory The word "democracy" is never mentioned. The preference is expressed without naming, o r describing, producing, or the form of government it represents, so a f o r t ~ o rwithout ~ even suggesting, a rationale for that preference. When I came to the conception of good statesmanship which is expressed by his use of the phrase "the royal art," I contrasted it sharply with the use of the same phrase by Xenophon's Socrates, pointing out that while the latter is a p o l i t ~ c a ldoctrine in the strict sense of the term (it stipulates the conditions of legitimacy of the tenure of political power), the former is properly speaking a moraldoctrine: it defines only the moral dimension of the statesman's vocation. That this moral doctrine has far-reaching political ~ m p l i c a t ~ o nissclear enough, since it obliterates the distinction between the beautiful people and the necessary people which was the moral basis for the disfranchisement of large segments of the working population in the oligarchies. This feature of Socrates'thought could be expressed in Greek by the term difmotikos, used by orators and historians t o designate the attitude of one who is well-disposed towards the people, who isphilodemos instead of muodFmos. There is no proper counterpart to dFmotikos in English; the nearest we can come t o it is by an extended use of "democratic." In that extended use of the term we can say that Socrates'conception of the "royal art" IS democratic, though "demophilic" would be less misleading. The sentiment which it expresses in contrast to that conveyed by the use of the same phrase in Xenophon's account of Socrates may best be captured by projecting the two conceptions on an ideal plane: Imagine that all our hopes for what is good, beautiful and sensible for men and women were fulfilled. Then, if we follow Xenophon's Socrates, the spirit and structure of that fair city's government would be profoundly oligarchic: the knowledge and vision of a privileged leisure class would rule the visionless multitude. Not so if we1 followed the Socrates of Plato's Socratic dialogues: there every one of us would have the royal art, each of us would pursue the "examined life," we would all the ruled in our individual lives by our personal knowledge and vision of the good. The business of government would be transacted for us, for our benefit, by hired technicians-economists, generals, diplomats, legal experts, and so on, appointed by us and responsible to us. These hirelings would be masters of state craft.24This would be their unique qualification for office-not mastery of the royal art: this would belong n o more to them than to the rest of us as the inalienable privilege of our pursuit of the life of virtue.

510

POLITICAL THEORY / NOVEMBER 1983

But what of the real Athens-the actual city, which no one, by any stretch of the imagination, could think might come to be ruled, under its present constitution, by wisdom direct~ngevery civic actlvity towards a single imperious end-perfection of soul? Did Socrates hold views subversive of "the established constitution,"2s as those who prosecuted him and many of those who had voted against him had believed? In this article I have offered evidence that contrary answers must be given to this question, depending on whether or not we are to believe Xenophon or Plato. If we believe Xenophon, our answer must be, 'Yes, they wereprofoundly so.'The attack on election by lot would not of itself compel this answer. The lot was vulnerable to criticism on philodemic grounds. As we know from Isocrates, one could take pot-shots at it without surrendering one's claim t o be a loyal democrat.26 What would be fatal to that claim is the conviction that, in the phraseology of T I 1 above, only he who "knows how to rule" is a true "ruler," I. e., that entitlement to office is contingent on satisfying a condition which only a small minority of Athenians could hope to satisfy. expertise in statecraft comparable to that of accomplished craftsmen in the performing or productive arts. It would follow from this view that to randomize distribution of offices over a civic body in which "the most feeble and most stupid" (TI 5) greatly outnumber the capable and intelligent would be to insure, by the laws of statistical probability, that the great majority of those offices would go to people whose tenure of office lacks legitimacy The order of the magistrate would then have no authority unless a d hoc evidence were available that it proceeded on the requisite knowledge of statecraft. And the verdicts of the courts would have no authority, for who would want to argue that a majority of 201 or 501 or 1001 lot-selected jurors were knowledgeable jurists? T o save the legitimacy of Athenian government in the face of such a root-andbranch rejection of its procedures one might dredge up that curious bit of legal positivism in Book IV of the M e r n ~ r a b i l i awhich, ~~ so surprisingly, identifies the just with the legal. But this would be unavailing. For Athenian positive law, made in the last analysis by lot-selected legislative commissions or by the sovereign Assembly, would itself lack authority, since in those bodies those who d o have knowledge of statecraft would be greatly outnumbered by those who don't. Not so, if we are to go by what we learn in Plato's earlier dialogues. While Socrates there repeatedly makes unforgivably intemperate allegations of wrongdoing in Athenian public life and attacks pay for public office, whose effect on the character he considers corrupting (Gorg.

Vlastos 1 SOCRATES A N D ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

51 1

5 1 5 ~ ) , 2 he 7 ~never attacks any other Athenian institution, never says a word against election by lot, never says, or directly implies, that knowledge of statecraft is a condition of legitimate civic authority He tells his friend in the privacy of his prison cell, where he could have no motive for dissembling, that he prefers the laws of Athens to those of any other state known to him. He does not question the moral authority of the court which condemned him even though he thinks its verdict most unjust. He gives morally weighty reasons, consistent with all his other views, why every Athenian is morally obligated to obey every legal order by its officers unless he considers it unjust, in which case he may protest its injustice but must consent to punishment if his protest proves unavailing.28 Both in his doctrines and in his personal conduct Plato's Socrates is profoundly and consistently loyal to the Athenian constitution. Who then is the true, historical, Socrates? Xenophon's or Plato's? Which of the two I believe it is, you have already guessed. A declaration of faith on my part in this last gasp of the lecture would be redundant. What you would like is not faith, but knowledge-even afew crumbs of it would be better than nothing, if richer fare were unavailable. If your demand were as modest as that, I could meet it. I can offer you two good-sized crumbs. We d o know of two things which give us some reason for believing that the Socrates who preferred democracy to oligarchy is the true one: The first is his association with Chaerephon, of whose strongly democratic partisanship there is no doubt. In 404 B. C., when the junta, supported by the Spartan occupational force, ruled Athens, Chaerephon fled to join the resistance under Thrasybulus and fought with that band which, under desperate odds, liberated Athens. Chaerephon had been "from youth" (Apol. 21A1) Socrates' friend, his ardent, devoted disciple: Aristophanes makes him Socrates'deputy, almost his equal, in the Thinkery 29 What sense could be made of that, if Socrates had been a crypto-oligarch? The second thing is that Socrates had kept the admiration of Lysias, whose identification with the democratic cause is also beyond doubt: it is manifest in the lavish aid Lysias had given from his own purse t o the resistance movement and in the sentiments voiced in the speech he wrote for the Athenian who opposed the motion of Phormisius which, if passed, would have disfranchised 5000 landless Athenians.jo Lysias, who had known Socrates well, sprung to the defense of his memory in the debate that followed within a few years of his death, producing an Apology (schol. by Arethas on Plato, Apol. 18B), probably in rebuttal

512

P O L I T I C A L T H E O R Y / NOVEMBER 1983

of Polycrates' Accusation, whose attack on Socrates had been strongly political. If Lysias had thought Socrates an enemy of the restored democracy, he could not have entered the lists on his behalf in that debate. These wisps of inference give us some reason to believe that friends of Socrates, who staked their lives and fortunes on Athenian democracy at a time when ~ t surv~val s h ung on a thread, had felt that Socrates was on their side.31

NOTES 1. Thls paper represents work in progress. An earlier verslon of it was delivered on February 14, 1983, at the University of London as a n S. V Keeling Lecture and elic~ted helpful crlticlsms from colleagues w h o heard it there. These criticisms have been only partly met In the present verslon, which 1s the text of a n address presented six weeks later at a conference o n A n c ~ e n tGreek Political Theory at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York, organized by Professor Melvin Richter. I a m well aware that much still remains t o be done t o flesh o u t ~ t argument. s I consent t o ~ t publication s only because more presslng obligat~onswill keep me at other work for many months t o come. If in its still unfin~shedform it were t o s t ~ m u l a t eothers t o glve c r i t ~ c aattentlon l t o the truth for whlch it contends, ~t may perhaps serve a useful purpose. 2. F o r the use of these t w o texts t o illuminate T I I a m indebted t o K. R . Dover, "The Freedom of the Intellectual In Greek Society," Talanta 7 (1975), 24ff. 2A. Perlcles' most radical ~nnovation-pay for d i c a s t ~ cservlce-is specifically ascribed by Ar~stotle(Crr. 53B7-C3) t o Damon's "adv~ce." 3. F o r polit~cal~ m p l i c a t ~ o nins this charge see Crr. 57B-3, notlng the connection of "corrupter of the laws" at B7 w ~ t h"corruptor of young and unintelligent men" at C 2 3A. Attempts t o drlve a wedge between the discourse of the Laws and Socrates'own oplnions are repeatedly made. I have yet t o see evidence for them w h ~ c hstands u p to examination. Thus, most recently, Paul Woodruff (review of R. E. Allen, Socrates and Legal Obligarron, In the Journalof the History of Philosophy 21 [1983], 93ff. at 94) c l a ~ m s that the discourse "appeals t o the false vlew that how people react t o Socrates is morally relevantM(butthe a l l u s ~ o nat 54B7 is not t o "people" but "to your own people"-people for whose opinlon you d o care) and "appears t o presuppose the odious possibility that In cases not ~nvolvingparents a n d guardians it could be permissible t o return harm for harmn(but what is permissible at 54E6 is anriporern, nor anradikern and anrikakourgern, whlch are clearly ruled out at 54C2-3). 4. Explic~tlys o at 52E-53A5: "But you did not prefer e ~ t h e rSparta o r Crete, w h ~ c h you are always saying are well-governed, nor any other city, Greek o r b a r b a r ~ a n S o clear ~t 1s that t o you, above other Athenians, the city and we the laws are exceedingly pleasing: for whom would a c ~ t yplease w ~ t h o u tthe laws?" 5. Note 4 above subjin. 6 . Note 4 above.

7 Crr. 53B.

Vlastos / SOCRATES AND ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

513

8. That eunomersthor as applied to Sparta and Crete at 52E and to Thebes and Megara at 53B refers primarily to good observance of the laws (rather than to the possession of good laws as such) IS clear in the latter passage: that Thebes and Megara eunomountoi 1s glven as the explanation of the hostile reception Socrates would get in those cities if he arrlved there as jail-breaker and "corruptor of the laws." 9. In the converse case, when Socrates is accused of fomenting disrespect for the "laws" of Athens, ~ t constltutlon s is clearly what is meant. The passage In Xenophon quoted In T4 above continues: "Such arguments, sald he [the accuser], led the young to desplse the established constitution [a varlant expression for 'the established laws' at the start of the quotation] and made them violent." 10. Throughout thls paper I proceed on the hypothesis (for whlch I shall be argulng elsewhere) that In thls early part of h ~ corpus s (and only here ) Plato recreates vlews and arguments of the hlstorlcal Socrates, deplctlng them In conversations whlch are, for the most part, dramatlc fictlon rather than biography. For the dialogues whlch, In my vlew, fall lnto this part of the Platonlc corpus see my "Socratlc Elenchus," Oxford Studies rn Ancrent Philosophy I (1983), 17ff, nn. 2 and 65. 11. Gorg. 5 15C-5 16E. That the selection of these names cuts across party lines has often been notlced. Cimon, the staunch conservatlve, frlend of Sparta, flanks Perlcles, h ~ s archrlval, the architect of okra demokrotio, Arlstotle's bete norre. 12. A qulck look at the textual evldence these scholars clte for those oplnlons will show that, wlth but one exceptlon, all of ~t comes from Xenophon. The exceptlon 1s Prr. 319C-D: Having just polnted out that when some technical toplc 1s up for consideration before the Assembly, only expert testimony is welcome, Socrates proceeds:

But when there 1s need to deliberate about public policy, a builder will get up to advlse or acoppersmlth or a cobbler, a merchant, an Importer, rich or poor, of hlgh or low birth, and no one rebukes hlm, as In the former case, for offering advlce wlthout havlng acqulred any knowledge or ever havlng had a teacher. Clearly, they thlnk that [thls sort of knowledge] cannot be taught." T o find In thls remark "cruel scorn for the whole of Athenlan democracy" (Helnrlch Maler, 418, n. I) one would have to read lnto ~t the anti-democratic anlmus whlch Xenophon Imputes to Socrates. Otherwise there would be nothlng In the text to Indicate that the procedure here described 1s absurd or even the least b ~ unreasonable. t Conslder the debate on Mytilene (Thuc. 3,36ff.) and the ones that followed on Torone, Sclone, and Melos, as the war dragged on. One can hardly lmaglne aquestion of greater moral urgency than genoclde as an Instrument of lmperlal policy. If the Athenlans believed that moral expertise were available for consultation, Plato's Socrates (Cr. 47A48A) would Insist that this, and thls alone, should declde the issue. Believingas they do that ~tis unavailable, why should he think it unreasonable of them to open it up fordiscuss~onby everyone who is to share In moral responsibility for the decision? 13. The precise Import of the copula in this classical formula 1s a toplc for a separate Investlgatlon. For my purposes In the present essay lt suffices to glve it its mlnlmal sense, that of necessary Interentailment: all those who have vlrtue necessarily have knowledge and vlce versa. 14. He tells young Euthydemus, asplrant to political leadership In Athens: "You deslre that excellence through whlch men become poiitikoi and oikonomikor and capable of ruling and being useful both to others and to themselves. You deslre the noblest

514

POLITICAL T H E O R Y / N O V E M B E R 1983

excellence and the greatest art, for ~tbelongs t o k ~ n g and s IS called 'royal'"(Mem. 4,2, 11). 15. F o r ~ t moralcontent s see especially the dialogue with A r ~ s t ~ p p uMem. s, 2, 1. In the "royal art" (2, 1, 17) the latter sees a rule of life which Inures men t o that disciplined endurance of h a r d s h ~ pand sacrifice of gratification through which one earns one's place In the master-class. Thus the moral component of the "royal art" IS that characterlstlc X e n o p h o n t ~ cvirtue, enkrateia, w h ~ c h ,accoring to Xenophon, Socrates c o n s ~ d e r sthe "foundation (krepidalof all virtue"(Mem. 1 , 5 , 4 : cf. 2, 1, I and 4 , 5 , 1; In Plato's S o c r a t ~ c dialogues enkrateia IS never s~ngledout as a special virtue o n a par w ~ t hthe canonical five-the word enkrarera never occurs In the S o c r a t ~ cdialogues, only the adject~ve enkrates [once, In 11s commonplace use, Gorg. 491Dl). 16. A t t a c h ~ n g s u p r e m eImportance t o the first two (to both of them ~nconjunction, for he takes them to be closely interconnected: see the dialogue w ~ t hNicomachides, Mem. 3, 4), Socrates enjoins expertise In them t o those who hold h ~ g hoffice in Athens o r who asplre, o r should asplre, t o it: t o Per~cles'son,now general (Mem. 3,5), t o Glaucon (3,6), to C h a r m ~ d e s(3, 7). In marked contrast to the Socrates depicted in Plato's S o c r a t ~ c dialogues, Xenophon's Socrates appears t o be h ~ g h l yexpert in public finance and military e these areas to Pericles and t o Glaucon sclence: he IS In a positlon t o offer detailed a d v ~ c in (Mem. 3, 5-6). 17 Phormis~us'proposalt o restrlct cit~zenshipt o those who owned land, w h ~ c hwould have disfranch~sedno more than 5,000-approx~mately a quarter of the C I V I C body (sadly depleted by the preceding civil war) strikes the highborn A t h e n ~ a nwho opposes ~t as expressing the sentiments of those "who In their heart were with the men of the c ~ t y [the oligarchs who supported the Thirty] and only by a c c ~ d e n found t themselves on the slde of the men of Peiraeus [the democrats under Thrasybulus]" ( L y s ~ a s Or. , 34, 2 [C. Hude, ed. (Oxford, 1912)l.) 18. In an earlier study ("lsonomia PolitikF,"first published In 1964, r e p r ~ n t e dIn my Platonrc Studies [Princeton, 1973; second edition, 19811, 164ff. at 179, nn. 63-64) I allow that the figure m ~ g h tbe slightly h ~ g h e rthan 50% notlng, however, that ps.-Herodes, Perr e t o the rest [of the natlve p o p u l a t ~ o n ] Politelas (30,3 1) "gives the 1:3 ratlo of a c t ~ v cltizens as the smallest in the oligarchies established by Sparta (at the end of the Peloponneslan War)." Martln Ostwald, Nomos a n d the Begrnnrngs of Athenran Democracy (Oxford, 1966) 118, nn. 3 and 5, favors the 1:3 ratlo and is cited as the authority for that figure In Nancy Demand, Thebes in the Fifth Century (London, 1982), p. 16. J . M. Moore, Aristotle a n d Xenophon o n Democracy a n d Oligarchy (London, 1975), 129, opts for a higher figure: "a little under one half the p o p u l a t ~ o nhad full rights." 19. See also the s ~ m i l a description r of the teacher whose misslon IS t o care for souls In the Lnches (1868): t o qualify one should be able t o show "which Athenians o r aliens, slaves o r freemen, have become admittedly good men because of him." 20. Note the place of the oikonomikos In the descript~onof the "royal art" in Mem. 4 , 2 , I I, cited in n. 14 above. Both economlc and military sclence are prime qualifications for those who are, o r should be, holding h ~ g hpolitical office: n. 16 above. t 21. As IS clear at T 2 I, even the appeasement of C I V I C strife-to which Socrates m ~ g h be expected to attach direct moral ~mportance-1s excluded from the scope of the royal art. 22. "To this art both the general's and the other arts [of the economlst, doctor, et at.. 289A5-61 turn over their several products t o be governed by ~ tslnce , only 11knows how t o use themV(Euthyd. 29IC7-9). The notlon that this art should d o the work of the general, economlst, and the like, IS debunked in the dece~tfulfantasy ("dream of horn") In the Charm. (173A-D) where moral w ~ s d o m(sophr5synZ) IS glven the job of i n s u r ~ n gthat the

Vlastos / SOCRATES A N D ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

515

various craftsmen ("doctor, general, or anyoneelse"[17382-31) should do the11work wlth techn~calc ompetence (technikos): if,per irnpossibile, the job were done, we would still not know if, as a result, "we would do well and would be happy" (173D4). 23. Note the conjunction, "men and women,"in T I 8 above. For Socrates moral vlrtue IS the same In women as in men (Meno 72D-73B). 24. This is what Socrates t h ~ n k sthe holders of governmental office should be: craftsmen hired to ply their craft for the exclusive benefit of the governed (Rep. I, 346E-347D). 25. Cf. T4 above in conjunction with n. 9. 26. Areop. 23: Our ancestors thought election ek prokrrton "more favorable to the people (&motikoteran)than was sortitlon: under the latter chance would decide the Issue and a partlsan of oligarchy would often get the office. "Elsewhere (Platonic Studies, pp. 186-188, and nn. 87 and 88) I have argued agalnst classify~ngIsocrates as a prooligarch~cAthenian. A man whose proposed reforms, however reactionary, entail no disfranchisement of landless and banausic citlzens and leave the demos with the sovereign power "to appoint the magistrates, p u n ~ s hmisdemeanors and adjudicate disputes [i.e., w ~ t hplenary electlve and judiclai powers]" (Areop. 26, and cf. Panath. 147), is not an advocate of oligarchy. 27 Mem. 4, 4, 12: Socrates: "I say that what IS legal (nomrmon) is just." Hippias: "Socrates, d o you mean that the legal and the just are the same?" Socrates: "1 do." 27A. Though the attack 1s Indirect (Pericles IS reproached for having made the Athemans "idle and cowardly and talkative and greedy, havrng bern the first to establish pay for public office"), it is clear enough and I do not wlsh to underest~mateits Importance. It warrants the Inference that h ~ political s sentimezts were conservat~ve--which would be ent~relyconsistent with the preference for democracy over oligarchy, as we know from the case of Isocrates. 28. Crr. 5 1 B8-CI: "In war, In law-court, everywhere, one must do what one's city and fatherland commands or persuade her as to the nature ofjustice." For the lnterpretatlon of thls much debated text I a m indebted to R . Kraut, "Plato's Apology and Crito: Two Recent Studies" (Ethics 91 [1981], 651ff. at 664): "The cltlzen may disobey but only on c o n d i t ~ o nthat he justify h ~ sact In an appropriate forum. The persuade-or-obey doctrine IS the S o c r a t ~ canalogue t o the contemporary doctrine of consc~entiousrefusal." The case for Kraut's textual exegesls will be strengthened if we note that In the c ~ t e dtext the verbpeltho; whlch comes through the translat~onsas "persuade," is, unlike the latter, not a "success-verb". thus Socrates In the Apology spends all day long "persuading"(30E7, 31 B5) people whom he does not convince. If Socrates had believed that he wasjustified In disobey~nga legal command only if he had reasonable prospects of c o n v ~ n c ~ na gcourt of law that the command was unjust, the effect~vescope of permissible disobedience would be sadly reduced. 29. For the references see my revlew of Ellen and Neal Wood, Clasp Ideolog~sa n d Ancient Politrcal Theory, in Phoenrx 34 (1980), 347ff. at 351. 30. For the references see my revlew of The Accusers of Socrates (in Greek) by E. N. Plat~s,In American Journal of Philology 104 (1983), 201ff. at 206. 31. I want to record my g r a t ~ t u d eto the Hastings Center for appolntlng me Senior Visltlng Scholar d u r ~ n g1982-1983. Thls artlcle 1s a partial outcome of studies In the philosophy of Socrates whlch my res~denceat the Center enabled me to pursue under ideally congenial and lnvlgorating conditions.

516

POLITICAL THEORY i NOVEMBER 1983

Gregory Vlastos is Stuart Professor of Philosophy, Emeritus, at Princeton. In recent years he has been Mills Visiting Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of California, Berkeley. During the present academic year he IS Distinguished Professorial Visiting Fellow at Christ S College, Cambridge University. He was John Locke Lecturer in Oxford in 1960, Gifford Lecturer at the University of St. Andrews in 1981. He IS a member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and Corresponding Fellow of the British Academy. Hispublications have been mainly in the area of Greek philosophy.

Vlastos, The Historical Socrates and Athenian Democracy.pdf ...

There was a problem loading more pages. Retrying... Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps.

508KB Sizes 2 Downloads 198 Views

Recommend Documents

Vlastos, The Historical Socrates and Athenian Democracy.pdf ...
Vlastos, The Historical Socrates and Athenian Democracy.pdf. Vlastos, The Historical Socrates and Athenian Democracy.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In.

Athenian Democracy & Empire
Jun 7, 2005 - lowed the Athenians to keep her subjects in line if they should attempt ... Since the Athenians controlled the Aegean it was very easy for them to restrict trade ..... democracies; anyone who has taken a junior high school social.

Misunderstanding Socrates
meek and compliant auditors on themes as diverse as art, mathematics, politics, and ... phro's definition of piety is false (i.e., not-p), and recom- mends a revised ...

socrates column.pdf
Sign in. Page. 1. /. 4. Loading… Page 1 of 4. Page 1 of 4. Page 2 of 4. Page 2 of 4. Page 3 of 4. Page 3 of 4. socrates column.pdf. socrates column.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying socrates column.pdf. Page 1 of 4.

Vlastos, Ethics and Physics in Democritus (16p).pdf
r4OSo should, of course, not be read in the Aristotelian. sense of "passion", but in the Hippocratic sense of "disease", as e.g. in On Airs,. Waters, etc., 22, ravTG T&ri irica Ec&a. 8 As one would expect, there are exceptions, when the medical men t

Burnyeat, Barnes, Socrates and the Jury, Paradoxes in Plato's ...
Burnyeat, Barnes, Socrates and the Jury, Paradoxes in ... to's Distinction between Knowledge and True Belief.pdf. Burnyeat, Barnes, Socrates and the Jury, ...

The Theology Xenophon's Socrates
Page 1 ..... god per se, but rather the existence of 'god understood as a ... creator'; he takes this to be the general logical form of arguments from design. ... or creator. Socrates and Aristodemus appear to be uninterested in con- a way that will.

The Great Contraction and the Current Crisis: Historical ...
Apr 24, 2009 - Recovery was quickly spurred by the floating of the dollar in April 1933 and massive gold purchases by the Treasury which increased the.