Economics Letters 105 (2009) 145–147

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Economics Letters j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w. e l s ev i e r. c o m / l o c a t e / e c o l e t

Monotonic incompatibility between electing and ranking☆ Michel Balinski a,b,⁎, Andrew Jennings c, Rida Laraki a,b a b c

Département d'Économie, École Polytechnique, 91128 Palaiseau cedex, France C.N.R.S., France Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Arizona State University, USA

a r t i c l e

i n f o

Article history: Received 9 June 2009 Received in revised form 24 June 2009 Accepted 30 June 2009 Available online 13 July 2009

a b s t r a c t Borda proposed to assign points to each of m candidates. Condorcet proposed to assign points to each of m! rankings of candidates. One is appropriate for electing, the other for ranking. They satisfy different types of monotonicity that are incompatible. © 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Borda Condorcet Incompatibility Electing Ranking JEL classification: D71

1. Introduction The traditional model of social choice assumes that each of n judges or voters submits a rank-ordering of all the m candidates. Two foremost questions are addressed: (1) the designation of a winner, (2) the designation of a ranking of all the candidates in the order of their merit. The Chevalier de Borda's method assigns points to candidates. A voter contributes k Borda-points to a candidate C if k candidates are ranked below C. The Borda-score of a candidate is the sum of her/his Borda-points. The Borda-winner is the candidate with the highest score. The Borda-ranking is established in a descending order by the candidate's Borda-scores. The Marquis de Condorcet had an entirely different idea. A voter with the rank-order Q contributes k Condorcetpoints to a rank-order1 R if the two rankings agree in k pair-by-pair comparisons. The Condorcet-score of a ranking is the sum of its Condorcet-points over all voters. The Condorcet-ranking is the ranking with the highest score.2 By definition, the Chevalier and the Marquis addressed different questions. Condorcet himself seems to have realized that the two

☆ This work started during the visit of Andrew Jennings to the Ecole Polytechnique in 2008 and was partially supported by G.I.S. Sciences de la Décision. ⁎ Corresponding author. Tel.: +33 169333010; fax: +33 169333427. E-mail address: [email protected] (M. Balinski). 1 Note that there are m! rankings. 2 This is the same rule suggested independently by John Kemeny. 0165-1765/$ – see front matter © 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.econlet.2009.06.024

ideas (choosing and ranking) diverged, as Peyton Young (Young, 1988) pointed out after a careful reading of his works. The divergence may be shown by a simple example. The notation A ≻ B indicates that a voter ranks candidate A ahead of candidate B, A ≈ B that she/he considers them tied, and A ⪰ B that A ≻ B or A ≈ B. The symbols ≻S, ≈ S, and ⪰S indicate society's ranking determined by a social decision method. Consider the profile3 333 : A  B  C

333 : B  C  A

333 : C  A  B

1 : A  C  B; meaning, for example, that 333 voters have the ranking A ≻ B ≻ C. The first 999 voters constitute a Condorcet-component: every candidate appears in every position exactly the same number of times. In the absence of the last voter, there is a clear tie between all three candidates—the perfect symmetry in the voter profile demands it. Accordingly, the last voter tips the scales and causes A to be the winner and B to be the loser. Borda's method yields this outcome. However, A ≻S C ≻S B is certainly not society's preferred ranking. Only one voter prefers it. 333 are directly opposed. There are two Condorcet-rankings: A ≻S B ≻S C and C ≻S A ≻S B. In each case 333 voters most prefer it, and both strictly dominate the Borda-ranking in the pair-by-pair comparisons. On the other hand, Condorcet's method yields a tie in winners, A and C, which is unacceptable as well.

3

Originally in (Balinski and Laraki, 2007). For details see (Balinski and Laraki, 2010).

146

M. Balinski et al. / Economics Letters 105 (2009) 145–147

Another recurring and fundamental question in social choice is that of monotonicity. There are many different conceptual formulations of monotonicity (see Maskin, 1999; Muller and Satterthwaite, 1977; Smith, 1973). Choice-monotonicity (Smith, 1973) requires that when A is ranked higher than B by society and some voters raise A in their rankings, A is still ranked above B. Rank-monotonicity requires that when A is the winner and some voters raise A in their rankings, the entire ranking of society is preserved. It is proven that Borda is choice- but not rank-monotone, Condorcet is rank- but not choicemonotone. No unanimous and impartial4 method is rank- and choicemonotone. A counter example with five candidates shows that Condorcet is not choice-monotone. Five candidates implies 120 possible outputs, so the search was difficult. No counter example exists with fewer candidates.

Table 1 Pairwise relative reward table for P0. Versus A B C D E

A −2 1 −k + 2 2

B

C

D

E

2

−1 k–2

k–2 k–2 k–2

−2 k–2 −1 2

−k+2 −k+2 −k+2

−k + 2 1

−2

Table 2 Remaining rankings after one step. BCADE R2 = BECAD ABCED

BAECD BEACD R1 = ABCDE

BACED BCEAD ABECD

BACDE BCAED

2. Choice-monotonicity Consider any pair of candidates A and B for which a method of ranking yields A ⪰ S B in society's ranking. The method is choicemonotone if one or more voters move A higher or B lower implies A ≻S B. This definition includes the requirement that ties can be broken simply by having one voter move one of the tied candidates up or down one position. Condorcet's method is not choice-monotone. The counter example uses only a weak form of choice-monotonicity (no need to break ties). Consider the following voter profile, P 0 : k:ABCDE k:BECAD 2:DECAB 1:DCEAB 1:DEACB If k is at least 4, then Condorcet's method will give a two-way tie for the first between R1 = A S B S C S D S E

and

R2 = B S E S C S A S D:

This can be checked easily enough with a computer, but if k is at least 7, a simple proof follows. The relative pairwise rewards for one candidate preceding another in society's ranking are given in Table 1. For simplicity, the mean, k + 2, has been subtracted from each element5. This decreases the Condorcet-score of each ranking by 10(k + 2), but does not affect the order of finish. The rankings R1 and R2 both have a relative Condorcet-score of 5k–10, and it will be seen that no other ranking can have as high a score. Any ranking which fails to preserve all five of the most significant pairwise relationships, A ≻ D, B ≻ C, B ≻ D, B ≻ E and C ≻ D, may score at most 3k + 2 (the sum of at most 3k − 6 from these five pairs and no more than 8 points from the other five pairs). For k ≥ 7, this is less than 5k–10 so any ranking which doesn't satisfy these five significant relationships is excluded from winning. Out of the 120 possible societal rankings, there are 11 which meet this criterion, given in Table 2. 4 Impartiality requires that when the names of the candidates or of the voters are labeled differently, the ranking does not change. Implicitly, ties are admitted in the outputs. 5 E.g., the reward from A ≻ C is k + 1 Condorcet-points because k + 1 voters rank A above C. When k + 2 is subtracted, − 1 appears in the third column of the first row of the table.

The chosen rankings R1 and R2 both have total contributions of 0 points from the eight less-significant pairwise relationships. It is impossible for any ranking with B ≻A, A ≻ E, and C ≻E to achieve first place, as this would contribute (−2)+ (−2)+ (−1)= −5 Condorcetpoints, to which only 3 points could be added by the other two rankings. It is also impossible for any ranking with A ≻E, E ≻D, and A ≻C to achieve first place, since this would also contribute (−2) + (−2) + (−1)= −5 Condorcet-points, to which only 3 points could be added by the other two rankings. This eliminates 7 of the rankings, leaving those in Table 3. Two are the chosen rankings. The Condorcet-scores of the remaining two are computed below, where C(R) indicates the Condorcet-score of ranking R (without the 5k–10 point contribution from the five most significant pairs), and PXY indicates the pairwise relative reward for a ranking that places candidate X above candidate Y. C ðBEACDÞ = PBA + PAC + PEA + PEC + PED = ð−2Þ + ð−1Þ + 2 + 1 + ð−2Þ = − 2

C ðBCEADÞ = PBA + PCA + PEA + PCE + PED = ð−2Þ + 1 + 2 + ð−1Þ + ð−2Þ = − 2 Thus the two rankings R1 and R2 are tied for first with Condorcet's method and this profile of voters. This profile is used to show that Condorcet's method fails choicemonotonicity. First, create profile P 1 from P 0 by having one of the voters who ranked C immediately above A swap them. Since this would cause any ranking which placed A above C to increase by one point and any ranking which placed C above A to decrease by one point, Condorcet's method now gives a unique best societal ranking of R1 = A ≻S B ≻S C ≻S D ≻S E. Second, create profile P 2 from P 0 by having the voter who ranked A immediately above C swap them. Then Condorcet's method would give a unique best societal ranking of R2 = B ≻S E ≻S C ≻S A ≻S D. Thus, moving from profile P 1 to P 2 is accomplished by having two

Table 3 Remaining rankings after two steps. R2 = BECAD BCEAD

BEACD R1 = ABCDE

M. Balinski et al. / Economics Letters 105 (2009) 145–147

voters who placed C immediately below A swap them, and this causes society's preferred ranking to change from R1 = A S B S C S D S E

to

R2 = B S E S C S A S D:

So the societal ranking has changed from C ≻S E to E ≻S C when C was moved strictly higher in two voters' rankings. The example requires five candidates. There is no-counter example for fewer. Among three candidates any violation of choice-monotonicity would be a pair of profiles where the unique winning ranking goes from A1 S A2 S A3

to

A3 S A2 S A1

when A2 is ranked higher by one or more voters. But when A1 ≻S A2 ≻S A3 is the unique winner, it must have more Condorcet-points than A1 ≻S A3 ≻S A2. After some voters have ranked A2 higher, this requires that A2 ≻S A3 ≻S A1 have more Condorcet-points than A3 ≻S A2 ≻S A1. Hence, it is impossible to find a violation of choice-monotonicity from the domain where Condorcet's method gives a unique best societal ranking. The method could be extended with a tie-breaking rule. This would strip the method of its impartiality or may cause it to fail choice- or rank-monotonicity in accord with the theorem below. For four candidates the proof is longer. 3. Incompatibility A method is rank-monotone if when one or more voters rank the winner higher society's ranking remains the same (as well as the winner). This requirement rejects many methods, including Borda's6. But it is easy to check that Condorcet's method satisfies rankmonotonicity. Theorem 1. There is no ranking-function that is impartial, unanimous, rank- and choice-monotone (when there are at least three candidates and at least two voters). Proof. Let 2k + i equal the number of voters, with i either 0 or 1, and P be the profile k : A  B  C  A 1  : : :  An

k : B  C  A  A1  : : :  An

i : A≈B≈C  A1  : : :  An : By impartiality, the profile k : B  A  C  A1  : : :  An

k : B  C  A  A1  : : :  An

i : A≈B≈C  A1  : : :  An implies A ≈ SC. The profile P is obtained when the first k voters move A above B. By choice-monotonicity, profile P must imply A ≻S C. Similarly, the profile k : A  B  C  A1  : : :  An

k : B  A  C  A1  : : :  An

i : A≈B≈C  A1  : : :  An

6 In the profile 3:A ≻ B ≻C and 2:C ≻B ≻A, the candidates A, B, and C receive 6, 5, and 4 Borda points respectively, giving the societal ranking A ≻S B ≻S C. If the two voters who rank A last were to raise him one position, this would reward A with two Borda points at the expense of B, giving a societal outcome of A ≻S C ≻S B.

147

implies A ≈ S B and changes into profile P when the second group of voters moves C above A. Thus the profile P must imply B ≻S A. Unanimity now determines the complete outcome for P to be B ≻S A ≻S C ≻S A1 ≻S ⋯ ≻ An. By rank-monotonicity, the profile k : B  A  C  A1  : : :  An

k : B  C  A  A1  : : :  An

i : A≈B≈C  A1  : : :  An ; must imply the same outcome as P, including A ≻S C, which contradicts the earlier impartiality result (A ≈S C) for this profile. □ This proof admits inputs with equivalents: they are not strict rankorders. The same proof is valid for strict rank-orders as inputs when i = 0. The theorem requires impartiality, a standard requirement for any real voting system, but a quite strict requirement in theoretical social choice. Can this requirement be weakened? Consider the method where, for n candidates, a sequence of “decisive” voters, v1,v2,…,vn−1, is chosen. v1's winner is society's winner; v2's preferred candidate of the remaining candidates is society's second choice; and so on. This method is equivalent to a dictatorship if and only if v1 = v2 = ⋯ = vn−1. It is unanimous, choicemonotone, and rank-monotone for any number of candidates. It is impartial with respect to candidates, though not to voters. In the same spirit, one can construct a unanimous choice- and rank-monotone method that is impartial with respect to voters. Consider the ordered set of candidates A1, A2,…, An, and the choice rule that chooses Ai as the winner if A1,…, Ai−1 are not ranked first by any voters and Ai is ranked first at least once. (Ai will win if he is the favorite of any voter and An will win only if he is the favorite of all voters.) After a winner is chosen, repeatedly applying the rule to the remaining field will choose second-place, third-place, etc., an entire societal ranking. References Balinski, M., Laraki, R., 2007. A theory of measuring, electing and ranking. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA 104, 8720–8725. Balinski, M., Laraki, R., One-Value, One-Vote: Measuring, Electing and Ranking (tentative title), MIT Press, to appear, 2010. Maskin, E., 1999. Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Review of Economic Studies 66, 23–38. Muller, E., Satterthwaite, M., 1977. The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy-proofness. Journal of Economic Theory 14, 412–418. Smith, J., 1973. Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41, 1027–1041. Young, H.P., 1988. Condorcet's theory of voting. American Political Science Review 82, 1231–1244.

Monotonic incompatibility between electing and ranking

Jul 13, 2009 - Proof. Let 2k+i equal the number of voters, with i either 0 or 1, and P ... implies A≈SC. The profile P is obtained when the first k voters move.

130KB Sizes 1 Downloads 124 Views

Recommend Documents

A theory of measuring, electing, and ranking
May 11, 2007 - in 1433 (2–4). © 2007 by The National Academy of Sciences of the USA. 8720 – 8725 ... best resist strategic manipulations of judges and voters under varying assumptions .... schools and universities. Formally, a common ...

A theory of measuring, electing and ranking
May 11, 2007 - Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article - sign up in the box. Rights & .... We add to this list a negative theorem of a new kind: ...

Self-incompatibility .pdf
devised diverse means of pollination by which the fertile pollen grains are able to reach the. receptive stigmas. Landing of pollen grains on the female stigma ...

Ghose, On the Incompatibility of Standard Quantum Mechanics and ...
Ghose, On the Incompatibility of Standard Quantum Mechanics and the de Broglie-Bohm Theory.pdf. Ghose, On the Incompatibility of Standard Quantum ...

Characterization of non-cytoplasmic incompatibility ...
and Florida, USA (James and Ballard, 2000). Its presence is also suspected ... Valerie Delmarre and Chantal Labellie for technical assistance. We are most ... Reproduction, Oxford University Press: Oxford. pp 42–80. Hoffmann AA, Turelli M, ...

Wolbachia and Cytoplasmic Incompatibility in the California Culex ...
(CI; reduced hatch rate) when infected males mate with uninfected females, can be used in a program ... 1Present address: Department of Entomology, North Carolina State tion; (2) ... between the two dorsal arms) within the accepted range for.

Monotonic iterative algorithm for minimum-entropy autofocus
m,n. |zmn|2 ln |zmn|2 + ln Ez. (3) where the minimum-entropy phase estimate is defined as. ˆφ = arg min .... aircraft with a nose-mounted phased-array antenna.

Non-Monotonic Self-Adjusting Computation
Abstract. Self-adjusting computation is a language-based approach to writing programs that respond dynamically to input changes by main- taining a trace of the computation consistent with the input, thus also updating the output. For monotonic progra

Wolbachia and Cytoplasmic Incompatibility in the ...
technical hurdles can be overcome, our data indicate that Wolbachia can invade ..... north-south transect in California during the summer of 1999 ...... and the University of California Mosquito Research Program. ... Applied Science, London.

What maintains noncytoplasmic incompatibility ...
invasion, are best understood by considering three factors: (i) ... that long term Wolbachia-host co-evolution would lead to reduced CI ..... female age, hard conditions in the field, and a long trip from Africa to ..... Accelerat- ing cytoplasmic dr

(eLASCA) By Monotonic Point Transformation
Apr 2, 2008 - enhanced laser speckle contrast analysis (eLASCA) method to improve ..... by Otsu multi-threshold method[25] in ITK software[26](bin=256 and.

ranking geral_valeEscolar.pdf
Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. ranking geral_valeEscolar.pdf. ranking geral_valeEscolar.pdf. Open. Extract.

Ranking Arizona - Snell & Wilmer
Apr 17, 2017 - ... business leaders throughout Arizona, participated in an online opinion poll ... company's revenue and number of employees. About Snell & Wilmer. Founded in 1938, Snell & Wilmer is a full-service business law firm with ...

RANKING MASCULINO.pdf
Page 1 of 1. RANKING MASCULINO.pdf. RANKING MASCULINO.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying RANKING MASCULINO.pdf.

RANKING EBA.pdf
em 6,2 milhões de animais, perdendo apenas para a China com 10,2 milhões de. Page 1 of 1. RANKING EBA.pdf. RANKING EBA.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with.

An oblique illusion modulated by visibility: Non-monotonic sensory ...
Aug 12, 2010 - this advantage for cardinal orientations have been exten- sively studied (e.g., the ..... mechanism hard wired in the brain. Further studies are ... involve an extended fronto-parietal brain network (Dehaene et al., 2006), or ...

Non-monotonic Reasoning Supporting Wireless Sensor ...
Sensor Networks for Intelligent Monitoring: The SINDI System ... a monitoring system that is able to reason about gathered data and support decisions. Most of the .... Application-wise, given the high variability among trials and studies address-.

The Evolution of Cytoplasmic Incompatibility Types
Dec 7, 2005 - Jan EngelstДdter,1 Sylvain Charlat, Andrew Pomiankowski and Gregory D. D. Hurst ...... low for small populations and remains constant up to a.

Bootstrapped Discovery and Ranking of Relevant Services and ...
There are several web-based ser- vices and .... TellMe, and conduct a live deployment and a web-based study .... Weather, Environment, Outlook, Temperature, .

Should a solution be aggregate monotonic?
May 31, 2006 - A solution of a coalitional#form game is said to be aggregate monotonic. (Megiddo, 1974) if no player is worse off whenever the worth of the grand coalition increases while the worth of all other coalitions remains unchanged. Aggregate

Website Ranking Bath.pdf
They are enjoying the luxury as a result of ... The Online Marketing strategy of the organizations is currently incorporated right into ... Website Ranking Bath.pdf.

Incompatibility of Pareto E ciency, Strategy-proofness ...
Incompatibility of Pareto E ciency, Strategy-proofness and Mutual Best. Umut Mert Dur∗. North Carolina State University. July 9, 2015. Abstract. While adopting a mechanism, a school board aims to have a reasonable balance between strategy-proofness

Entire Frame Image Display Employing Monotonic ...
May 6, 2014 - Notations kth partial sum. Pk = k. ∑ i=1. Ir i kth residue. Jk = I − Pk. Note: J0 = I is the initial (zeroth) residue. Yogesh Kumar Soniwal (IIT Kanpur). Monotonic NNMF & SNMSR. May 6, 2014. 6 / 49 ...

Website Ranking Bath.pdf
Page 1 of 60. Bohol Profile. Bohol. Basic Facts. Geographic Location Bohol is nestled securely at the heart of the Central. Visayas Region, between southeast of Cebu and southwest. of Leyte. Located centrally in the Philippine Archipelago, specifical