Reply to Paolo Bertoletti, “A Note on Third-Degree Price Discrimination and Output”∗ Takanori Adachi† January 29, 2004

Abstract The aim of this reply to Bertoletti (this Journal, 2004) is to give a “rational expectations” rationale for the demand system and the definition of consumer surplus in Adachi (this Journal, 2002).

I. Introduction In the literature of monopolistic third-degree price discrimination, it has been widely held that a change in aggregate Marshallian social welfare by price discrimination is negative if total output decreases.1 Among others, Schwartz (1990) verifies this conjecture for any total cost function that depends only on total output, not on its distribution among markets. Letting ∆X and ∆W denote a change in aggregate output and in social welfare, respectively, we can express his argument as follows: ∆X < 0 ⇒ ∆W < 0.

Bertoletti (2004) strengthens Schwartz’s (1990) result; he shows that social welfare must decrease by price discrimination even if total output remains constant. Again, using the same notation, we can describe his claim by ∆X ≤ 0 ⇒ ∆W < 0.

On the contrary, in Adachi (2002) I point out that when symmetric consumption externality between groups is considered, monopolistic third-degree price discrimination can improve social welfare even if total output remains the same, which seems contradictory to Bertoletti’s (2004) result. One might be tempted to say Bertoletti’s (2004) model is not general enough, or Adachi’s (2002) argument has some logical flaws. Neither is correct. To make clear this point, the present reply gives a “rational expectations” rationale for the demand system and the definition of consumer surplus used in Adachi (2002). ∗

I am grateful to Paolo Bertoletti and Francisco Galera, who independently made me realize the presentation problem in Adachi (2002). I also thank Pierre R´egibeau (Editor in charge). The usual disclaimer applies. An earlier version was circulated under the title “Addendum to A Note on Third-Degree Price Discrimination with Interdependent Demands.” † Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania, 3718 Locust Walk, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6297, USA. E-mail: [email protected] 1 See e.g. Stole (2003, Subsection 3.1).

1

Originally, I wrote Adachi (2002) as a note on Layson (1998) with intent to correct one of his results; that monopolistic third-degree price discrimination never improves social welfare if total output remains the same. At that time I interpreted consumption externality between groups as interdependency between group demands. I now realize that this interpretation is a misleading one, and I can no longer say that Adachi (2002) corrected one of the main results of Layson (1998) because his (and Bertoletti’s (2004)) micro foundation and mine are different. In particular, the statements below in Introduction of Adachi (2002) are no longer justified: “... In a recent paper in this Journal, Layson (1998) deals with the case of interdependent demands. He states that “if the demands are linear functions of prices and there is cross-price symmetry, then price discrimination lowers welfare” (p.521). However, his argument solely relies on the traditional lesson that “a robust sufficient condition for price discrimination to lower aggregate welfare is that total output remains the same or falls under price discrimination” (p.521). In fact, the author just verifies that ”[f]or the linear demand case with cross-price symmetry, the output effect of price discrimination is zero regardless of the slope of marginal cost” (p.520), and derives the above conclusion. He does not directly investigate the welfare change.” At the same time, however, the results in Adachi (2002) also make sense if what I explain in the following sections is understood. The bottom line is that in Adachi (2002) I wrote the demand system with the same notation as Layson’s (1998), though Adachi’s (2002) demand system is a conceptually different object from Layson’s (1998) and Bertoletti’s (2004).

II. Each Consumer Has a Unit Demand (Consumer Heterogeneity) In the model of Adachi (2002), there is a continuum of consumers, and each consumer in market i = 1,2 is indexed by xi ∈ [0, M] (M is so large a positive real number for a boundary solution to be excluded), and the expected number of customers who consume in market j = 1,2 is denoted by nej ∈ [0, M]. We assume that each individual can consume at most one unit of the good: if a consumer xi in market i purchases the good, he gains gross utility (ai − xi + ηnej ), where j 6= i, by paying the price pi ≥ 0, and if he does not purchase, he gains nothing. This is where consumer heterogeneity arises, and η is a constant which exhibits the effect of a consumption externality between two markets.2 For the law of demand to hold, we need to assume that 0 < η < 1 (meaning that the focus is not on negative externality but on positive externality). Lemma 1 in Adachi (2002) shows the existence of the lower bound η(α), where α ≡ a2 /a1 , for η to make the monopolist optimally supply a positive amount of the good to both markets under either the regime of uniform pricing or the regime of price discrimination.

III. Equilibrium Demand System As is the case in the literature of network externality such as Katz and Shapiro (1985), we confine our attention to the Rational Expectations Equilibrium (hereafter, REE) market 2

See Adachi (2004) for an analysis of the situation where there are consumption externalities within markets.

2

demands (that is, nei = qi for i = 1, 2). The terms qi and qj which appears in the equation (1) in Adachi (2002), pi = ai − qi + η · qj in market i 6= j (i, j = 1,2),

(1)

are such REE market demands. Considering REE market demands does not mean that we treat an arbitrary pair satisfying pri = ai − qir + η · qjr in market i 6= j under regime r = U, D,

(2)

where U means Uniform Pricing and D means Discriminatory Pricing. It rather means that we take the realized unique pair by the monopolist’s profit maximization (the existence can be checked), as the pair of aggregate demands. Essentially, it is possible to think that the monopolist directly decides a supply schedule (q1r , q2r ), under equality constraint (2), to maximize her profit. By the uniqueness, the solution of the monopolist’s optimization (profit maximization) without the constraint (q1r , q2r ) ∈ [0, M]2 is a unique alternative of the optimal supply schedule. Since in the following such qir is verified to be non-negative (note that M can be arbitrary large) under the present model, it is assured that the pair indeed exists as optimal quantities for the monopolist.

IV. Definition of Consumer Surplus under REE In REE, the net utility of consumer xi is expressed by (ai − xi + ηqjr − pri ), and Adachi (2002) defines the consumer surplus of each market i under the regime r by Z qir (q r )2 r CSi ≡ (3) [ai − xi + ηqjr − pri ]dxi = i , 2 0

which matches the definition of CS in Katz and Shapiro (1985, p.428, Equation (9)). Notice here that we are integrating the net utility with respect to xi . We do not use the demand system (1) when we calculate consumer surplus: our CSir is not derived from the demand system. This is because the demand system (1) just determines the equilibrium amount of demand. Hence, it is not the basis of welfare evaluation. This is exactly what makes a crucial difference between the model with consumption externality such as Adachi (2002) and the ones without such as Bertoletti (2004) and Galera (2002). We see this difference in the next section.

V. Definition of Consumer Surplus under the Representative Consumer Assumption To derive the market demands (1) and consumer surplus (3), we have supposed that each individual has a unit demand as explained in Section 2. Yet, there is another way to derive the market demands (1), which is based on the Representative Consumer Assumption (hereafter, RCA). The following accounts are based on Galera (2002). This approach starts with assuming that the demand system is determined as a solution of a representative consumer’s maximizing his utility, U (q) − p · q. In RCA, this U(q) − p · q itself is defined as consumer surplus. If we assume the following functional form: 3

1 U(q1 , q2 ) = a1 q1 + a2 q2 − (q12 + q22 − 2ηq1 q2 ), 2 then we can verify that maximizing utility with respect to q1 , q2 yields the same demand system as in (1). Now, let CSir be the consumer surplus of each market i under regime r with the above specification of the representative consumer’s utility. Galera (2002) shows that for each r, the following relationship holds (assuming the monopolist supplies a positive amount of the good to both markets under either regime): CS1r + CS2r = CS1r + CS2r − ηq1 q2 . Let ∆CS be the change in the sum of consumer surplus due to the regime change from uniform pricing to price discrimination. Then, Galera (2002) shows that ∆CS = −

3 (a2 − a1 )2 16 1 + η

(4)

whereas the corresponding object in Adachi (2002) is as follows: ∆CS = −

3 (a2 − a1 )2 . 16 (1 + η)2

(5)

This appears in the proof of Proposition 3 in Adachi (2002), which states that “price discrimination improves social welfare if and only if the value of the interdependency exceeds one half (1/2 < η (< 1)).” If we replace (5) by (4), then Proposition 3 does not hold any longer, that is, for any α ∈ (0, 1), price discrimination cannot improve social welfare for any η ∈ (η(α), 1). Moreover, Bertoletti (2004) generally shows that under RCA social welfare must decrease by price discrimination even if total output remains the same.

References [1] Adachi, Takanori. 2002. A Note on ‘Third-Degree Price Discrimination with Interdependent Demands. Journal of Industrial Economics 50: 235 (the main text is available at the JIE Notes and Comments Page, http://www.essex.ac.uk/jindec/notes.htm). [2] Adachi, Takanori. 2004. Third-Degree Price Discrimination, Consumption Externalities, and Social Welfare. Forthcoming in Economica. [3] Bertoletti, Paolo. 2004. A Note on Third-Degree Price Discrimination and Output. Forthcoming in Journal of Industrial Economics (the main text is available at the JIE Notes and Comments Page, http://www.essex.ac.uk/jindec/notes.htm). [4] Galera, Francisco. 2002. Personal Communication. [5] Katz, Michael L. and Carl Shapiro 1985. Network Externalities, Competition, and Compatibility. American Economic Review 75: 424-440. [6] Layson, Stephen K. 1998. Third-Degree Price Discrimination with Interdependent Demands. Journal of Industrial Economics 46: 511-524.

4

[7] Schwartz, Marius. 1990. Third-Degree Price Discrimination and Output: Generalizing a Welfare Result. American Economic Review 80: 1259-1262. [8] Stole, Lars A. 2003. Price Discrimination and Imperfect Competition. Mimeo, Chicago GSB (downloadable at http://gsblas.uchicago.edu/Lars Stole.html).

5

Reply to Paolo Bertoletti, “A Note on Third-Degree Price ...

Jan 29, 2004 - In REE, the net utility of consumer xi is expressed by (ai −xi +ηqr j −pr .... GSB (downloadable at http://gsblas.uchicago.edu/Lars Stole.html). 5.

139KB Sizes 1 Downloads 44 Views

Recommend Documents

Richard Rorty - On Ethnocentrism - A Reply to Clifford Geertz.pdf ...
Page 1 of 1. Page 1. Richard Rorty - On Ethnocentrism - A Reply to Clifford Geertz.pdf. Richard Rorty - On Ethnocentrism - A Reply to Clifford Geertz.pdf. Open.

A Note on the Inefficiency of Bidding over the Price of a ...
the class we consider, the price per unit share depends only on the first and ... (in the form of an independent audit) or endogenous (in the form of inter-agent.

On Swinburne's Reply
On Swinburne's Reply. Michael Martin. I am grateful for Professor Swinburne's comments1 on my paper “Swinburne on the. Resurrection”2 and I would like to address his concerns here. In particular let me explain why. Swinburne's dismissal of my cri

A Note on “Third-Degree Price Discrimination with ...
Mar 5, 2002 - that monopolistic third-degree price discrimination can improve social ... †Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania, 3718 Locust ...

Note on Drafting a speech.pdf
Page 1 of 1. Speech is supposed to be an oral presentation. But ,since you have speech as a discourse ,it is desirable. that we must learn the techniques of writing a speech.While presenting a speech on a stage, the speaker has a. lot of advantages .

Reply to Comment by Agrawal and Verma on ...
doi:10.1016/j.gca.2007.04.021. E-mail address: [email protected] www.elsevier.com/locate/gca. Geochimica et Cosmochimica Acta 71 (2007) 3391– ...

A note on Kandori-Matsushima
Sep 16, 2004 - Social Science Center, London, ON, N6A 5C2, Tel: 519-661-2111 ext. ... equilibria, where private information is revealed every T-periods, as δ ...

A Note to Forensics Parents
... from making comparisons during or after rounds- positive comments and good sportsmanship please! ... This is a major inconvenience for the Host school. 3.

A Note on -Permutations
We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Mathematical Association of America is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,

NFU reply to Commission Consultation on Bank Accounts.pdf ...
NFU reply to Commission Consultation on Bank Accounts.pdf. NFU reply to Commission Consultation on Bank Accounts.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In.

briefing note on - Services
systems. In the light of these conclusions, a series of meetings in Africa, including the Foresight. Africa workshop in Entebbe, the AU meeting of Directors for Livestock Development in. Kigali 2004, the Congress ... OIE meeting of SADC Chief Veterin

A note on juncture homomorphisms.pdf - Steve Borgatti
A full network homomorphism f: N -+ N' is a regular network homomorphism if for each R E [w fi( a) f2( R) fi( b) * 3 c, d E P such that fi(u) = fi( c), fi( b) = fi( d), cRb and uRd for all a, b E P. In a network N the bundle of relations B,, from a t

Reply to Shiner
My response will take the form of a series of questions followed by my own proposed .... assurances in his reply that ' it looks like Kristeller may not have been ...

Reply to Jackendoff
Unfair to facts. Philosophical Papers. J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock (eds.),. 154–174. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chomsky, Noam (2000). New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Fodor, Jerry (19

Note on commented games - GitHub
The starting point for debate upon a classic joseki. 4. An other ... At the start of this game, White made grave errors. ..... 3: At move 28, Black cannot start a ko.

Paolo Antognetti, Paolo Danielli, Alessandro De Gloria
level is usually interpreted by referring to two values vg and v, respectively .... report, Department of Computer Science, California Institute of. Technology, 1990;.

On good advice: a reply to McNaughton and Rawling Stephen Kearns ...
Please cite version published in Analysis 71:3, 2011, 506-8 (email [email protected] or [email protected] for a copy). 1. On good advice: a reply to McNaughton and ...

On Satan And Demons – A Reply To Anthony Buzzard
'Though the origin and ultimate fate of Satan are obscure, this is no excuse for not ...... was Galileo's understanding that the geocentric view of the universe was ...

On good advice: a reply to McNaughton and Rawling ...
On good advice: a reply to McNaughton and Rawling. Stephen Kearns and Daniel Star. David McNaughton and Piers Rawling (2011) take us to task for the following proposal: R: Necessarily, a fact F is a reason for an agent A to Φ iff F is evidence that

True, False, Paranormal and Designated: A Reply to Beall C.S. ...
C.S. JENKINS .... Of course, that only means its true-in-real-life that .5 ... Finally, of course, if one takes the second option, one places a familiar, and implausible, ...

Monotonicity and syllogistic inference: a reply to ...
For example, Crain and his colleagues have demonstrated that children as ... other hand, I concur with his criticism of the tentative explanation I suggested; but I ...

hell, vagueness, and justice: a reply to sider
All rights reserved. HELL, VAGUENESS, AND JUSTICE: A REPLY TO SIDER. Trent Dougherty and Ted Poston. Ted Sider's paper “Hell and Vagueness” challenges a ... sponses because our argument retains all the original premises of Sider's ..... Eye, whom

Moral parochialism misunderstood: a reply to Piazza ... - Colin Holbrook
Jan 22, 2016 - 4Department of Anthropology, University of California, Santa Barbara, Santa Barbara, CA ... judgements exist in all of the societies examined.

Moral parochialism misunderstood: a reply to Piazza ... - Colin Holbrook
Jan 22, 2016 - and Social Change, Arizona State University, ... 1Department of Anthropology and Center for Behavior, Evolution, and Culture, University of California, ... ness of an action (from wrong to not wrong or good) when it was.